Skip to main content

Is Love Beyond Our Control?

Perri Sriwannawit recently defended her PhD thesis in Philosophy at the University of Birmingham. This blog post is an adapted version of the discussion on romantic love in her PhD thesis.


Perri Sriwannawit

Harry Frankfurt (2004, p. 80) argues that love happens outside of our immediate control; we cannot control who we love or stop loving them on a whim. However, Frankfurt still suggests that love is free in an important sense. In this article, I will propose that love is only somewhat involuntary in the sense that he suggests, and that his notion of freedom is not the only way to explain freedom in love.

In Frankfurt’s (1971) earlier work, he argues that freedom of the will is grounded in the alignment of first-order desire (the desire that motivates us to act) and second-order volition (what we truly endorse as our desire). Frankfurt’s conception of freedom is not to do with whether we have voluntary control, but more to do with whether our volitional structure is aligned as such. What’s more, for Frankfurt (2004, p. 87), love itself is our own “configuration of the will”. In simple terms, our actions are shaped by what we love, and it is love that organises our will and guides our motivation.

Complications inevitably arise when we have conflicting loves. In these cases, Frankfurt (1998, p. 165) suggests that although we cannot fully control love, we can reflect on and prioritise our loves. And once we reach wholeheartedness, we can perhaps stop loving something that we love less in order to protect what we love more (Frankfurt, 2004, p. 46).

In my view, Frankfurt’s suggestion requires significant cognitive effort from the agent. Frankfurt (2004, p. 99) himself states that “wholeheartedness is difficult to come by”. Although he does not describe the process as cognitive work, it seems to be more than just a passive process of being guided by love. Frankfurt’s idea of resolving conflicting loves can be somewhat concretely described as follows: reflecting on and understanding our volitional structure, embracing what we love more, reaching wholeheartedness, and then letting wholeheartedness guide us to act in accordance with what we love more.

Frankfurt’s account of love heavily focuses on love that has already been cultivated and stabilised, and not on the uncertainties, hesitation, or the ebbs and flows that usually occur over the course of loving. In comparison, Natasha McKeever’s view is more accommodating to the complexities and dynamics of love, especially in its early stages. For example, everyday decisions can greatly influence love: decisions on how to spend Friday night, whether to ignore the beloved’s annoying habits, whether to move away, and so on (McKeever, 2019, p. 222). 

For McKeever, freedom in romantic love lies within the conscious choices and voluntary commitment we make to enter into the relationships, to maintain them, and in all other choices we make in the relationships. She suggests that the actions created by those choices constitute, to an extent, the love we experience. I agree with McKeever that relationship choices play some decisive role in love. And accordingly, love is also free in this way, rather than only in the way that Frankfurt suggests.

In sum, I propose that whilst love is largely beyond our immediate control, we still have control over love by making non-love-related choices and taking deliberate actions. That said, we should still be mindful that these choices cannot always determine whether love occurs, persists, or subsides in many cases.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...