Skip to main content

Getting (more or less) Rational Beliefs from Fiction

Greg is Professor of Philosophy at Nottingham (moving to York in September); Anna is doing her PhD with him. 

Greg Currie
We both work on the topics of fiction and imagination, and recently have become interested in the question of how our imaginative engagement with fictions influences our attitudes towards the real world – notably, our real-world beliefs. When we read Anna Karenina and become engrossed in the story of her life, what effects – if any – does this have on what we think, feel, desire about our own lives? Do we acquire new beliefs (or worries, or hopes...) about the real nature of love, or the evils of social conformity? To the extent to which we do that, how does it happen, and how rational is it?
 
Anna Ichino
These are in important respects empirical questions. In order to answer them we are looking at the psychological work in this area.

We have started by considering a growing body of studies that go under the heading of ‘Transportation studies’ (see Green & Brock 2000), which suggest that ‘being transported into a story-world’ tends to change readers’ attitudes in ways that reflect the views expressed, explicitly or implicitly, by the story in question. A story where a young girl is stabbed to death by an unrestrained psychiatric patient, even if explicitly labeled as fiction, seems to influence readers’ judgments about real levels of violence and injustice in the world. Psychologists in this field describe such attitudinal changes in terms of belief changes – and ones of a peculiarly irrational kind, which they call ‘narrative persuasion’. In this they are influenced by the work of Dan Gilbert, who argued for a ‘Spinozistic’ account of belief acquisition according to which we automatically believe everything we hear, while disbelieving means ridding ourselves of a belief already acquired: something requiring effort that, for various reasons, is not always forthcoming. Engagement with a fiction can be one of such reasons: stories absorb the readers’ attention, lowering their epistemic vigilance and preventing them from activating the appropriate processes of belief rejection. Readers’ epistemic vigilance might well be lowered also by the fact that they take the purpose of the narrator to be mere entertainment, rather than persuasion, so they’re even less motivated to assume a critical stance. This would explain why, according to some studies, readers tend to be even more influenced by fictional than by non-fictional stories (Prentice & Gerrig 1999).

These and other explanations of readers’ responses in terms of irrational belief changes might be questioned in various ways.

First, it might be questioned that what actually changes are readers’ beliefs. The evidence available so far doesn’t fully support this conclusion. That evidence consists of readers’ self-reports of agreement/disagreement expressed just after having read a story. But we know that people’s introspective reports of their own views are often inaccurate. Moreover, there is currently little evidence that tendencies to avow changed attitudes survive beyond the period immediately after reading. It seems tempting to conclude that, in most cases, readers’ avowals express fleeting emotional changes, rather than real changes of belief.

Second, even granting that fictions can change readers’ beliefs, we might question the irrationality of such changes. It might be perfectly rational – or, at least, not less rational than common processes of belief formation are – to take fictions as indicators of the serious opinions of their authors, and treat such inferred opinions as respectable candidates for beliefs, coming sometimes to embrace them. We very often get our opinions from the testimony of others, and are generally not very careful in judging the reliability of those we trust; trusting the author of a fiction ought not to be ruled out as essentially irrational.

Some support for the rationality of fiction-driven attitudinal change comes also from recent developmental work on children’s understanding of fiction. There is suggestive evidence not only that children at pre-school age can already distinguish fictional stories/characters from real ones, but also that they tend to be significantly less influenced by the former than by the latter (Richert & Smith 2011): a finding, this, in contrast with the above mentioned suggestion about the greater persuasive effects of fiction due to readers’ reduced vigilance. Moreover, it seems that insofar as children let themselves be influenced by fiction, they do that in a quite selective and critical way: they start quite early to develop and refine a good capacity to learn from fiction – making sensible decisions on what information included in a fictional story should be safely applied also to the real world, and what should not (Woolley & Cox 2007).

These two lines of inquiry – one on adults’ experiences of transportation into narratives and the other on the development of children’s fictional competence – have run quite separately from each other; and we notice some tension in the conclusions that psychologists tend to draw from them concerning the influences of fiction, respectively, on adults and on children. One of our aims is to form a consistent overall picture informed by these two research strands, and eventually to develop a theory of the various ways we are cognitively affected by fiction.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph