Joshua Cockayne |
Is belief in God irrational? William Clifford claimed that ‘It is wrong, always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence’ (1877) and this charge is often put to believers in God to demonstrate that their beliefs are irrational. I maintain that even if the publicly available evidence for the existence of God is ambiguous, that belief in God can be rational. I claim that a certain experience of God can immediately justify belief in God and thus render this belief rational. In what follows, I describe what it is to experience God and the epistemic value of such experience.
Typically, beliefs are concerned with knowledge that something is the case. For instance, I believe that there is thirty pounds in my wallet, I believe that I had a croissant for breakfast and I believe that I have a hospital appointment at three thirty this afternoon. All of these beliefs can be justified by appealing to publicly available evidence - namely, by looking in my wallet, checking my receipts, and reading today’s date in my diary.
However, some instances of belief cannot be easily understood as knowledge that something is the case. In her Wandering in Darkness, Eleonore Stump (2010) claims that there are some beliefs which are irreducible to propositions purporting to claim that something is the case. She cites Frank Jackson’s (1982) famous thought experiment of Mary. Stump maintains that Mary learns something new which is essentially non-propositional and irreducible to knowledge that. She then extends this example to think about our knowledge of persons, she writes:
Supposing Stump is right here, and there is something that Mary learns when she meets her mother that is irreducible to propositional knowledge that, what follows for belief in God? I claim that this insight can shed light on our original question of whether belief in God is rational.
If the God of the Christian Bible exists, for example, then we ought to understand God as a person who aims to have relationship with human beings. Furthermore, as Soren Kierkegaard (1844) claims, we ought to expect belief in God to arise from an encounter with the person of Jesus Christ. With Stump’s distinction in place, we can see why public evidence which purports to show that something is the case is an inadequate basis for belief in God as a person. Such evidence can only provide beliefs about God, and not beliefs in God. What is required for belief in God, I maintain, is an experience of God.
However, some instances of belief cannot be easily understood as knowledge that something is the case. In her Wandering in Darkness, Eleonore Stump (2010) claims that there are some beliefs which are irreducible to propositions purporting to claim that something is the case. She cites Frank Jackson’s (1982) famous thought experiment of Mary. Stump maintains that Mary learns something new which is essentially non-propositional and irreducible to knowledge that. She then extends this example to think about our knowledge of persons, she writes:
Imagine then that Mary in her imprisonment has had access to any and all information about the world as long as that information is only in the form of third-person accounts giving her knowledge….But she has never had any personal interactions of an unmediated and direct sort with another person. . . When Mary is first united with her mother, it seems indisputable that Mary will know things she did not know before, even if she knew everything about her mother that could be made available to her in non-narrative propositional form, including her mother’s psychological states. Although Mary knew that her mother loved her before she met her, when she is united with her mother, Mary will learn what it is like to be loved. . . . [W]hat will come as the major revelation to Mary is her mother. (2010: 52-3)
Supposing Stump is right here, and there is something that Mary learns when she meets her mother that is irreducible to propositional knowledge that, what follows for belief in God? I claim that this insight can shed light on our original question of whether belief in God is rational.
If the God of the Christian Bible exists, for example, then we ought to understand God as a person who aims to have relationship with human beings. Furthermore, as Soren Kierkegaard (1844) claims, we ought to expect belief in God to arise from an encounter with the person of Jesus Christ. With Stump’s distinction in place, we can see why public evidence which purports to show that something is the case is an inadequate basis for belief in God as a person. Such evidence can only provide beliefs about God, and not beliefs in God. What is required for belief in God, I maintain, is an experience of God.
Do such experiences occur? And can these experiences really justify belief in God? These two questions cannot be dealt with here in depth, but I will suggest how these might be broached. Firstly, it is an empirical question whether or not theistic believers purport to having had experiences which are rich enough to be considered experiences of God. However, for present purposes, it seems reasonable to assume that at least some sane individuals claim to have had such an experience.
Secondly, the most promising account of epistemic justification for these experiences, I claim, focuses on the ‘theistic seemings’ that theistic believers claim to have (see my summary of Michael Bergmann’s paper in my post on the Workshop on Defeat and Religious Epistemology, for example). Under such an account, theistic believers are justified in believing P, iff P seems to be the case and there is no defeating evidence for P. James Pryor (2000, 2004) has developed a defence of this kind of justification for perceptual beliefs, which I claim can be extended to belief in God.
If this account is correct, and theistic believers lack successful defeaters for the belief, then they are justified in believing that their personal experience of God is reliable. Furthermore, if this is true, then regardless of whether or not the public evidence is ambiguous, theistic believers are not irrational in continuing to believe.
If this account is correct, and theistic believers lack successful defeaters for the belief, then they are justified in believing that their personal experience of God is reliable. Furthermore, if this is true, then regardless of whether or not the public evidence is ambiguous, theistic believers are not irrational in continuing to believe.