Skip to main content

Psychiatric Kinds and Mental Harms

I am posting this on behalf of Nigel Sabbarton-Leary who has research interests in philosophy of science and metaphysics and more recently philosophy of psychiatry. Nigel co-edited with Helen Beebee a volume entitled Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds (Routledge, 2010).


Alternative Perspectives
on Psychiatric Validation

With Lisa Bortolotti and Matthew Broome I have recently written a paper on mental disorders and whether, or not, they should be construed as what philosophers call ‘natural kinds’. It will appear as a chapter in a volume entitled Alternative Perspectives on Psychiatric Validation, edited by Peter Zachar, Drozdstoj St. Stoyanov, Massimiliano Aragona, and Assen Jablensky for Oxford University Press (due out in November 2014). I thought I’d take this opportunity to articulate our position – in broad brush terms at least – and see what people thought.

First, a bit of preamble. By a ‘natural kind’ we mean an objective, mind-independent distinction in nature. The periodic table, for instance, is a fine example of a system of natural kind classifications; categories that latch on to real distinctions in nature.

In our paper we argue that not all of the categories set out in the various iterations of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM) actually pick out mental disorders. As such we counsel some conceptual revisions. Let’s call the categories of the DSM Psychiatric Kinds. Our claim is that Psychiatric Kinds can be divided into two discrete sub-categories: Mental Disorders and Mental Harms.

On our view Mental Disorders are caused by objective, mind-independent facts – specifically, some biological cause or other. Mental disorders, we say, are natural kinds. What we know about mental disorders of course is not perfect. There is a separate epistemic question as to whether or not we have been able to identify the particular cause of a suspected disorder. The point, however, is that a biological cause is a necessary condition of a mental disorder.

Mental Harms, in contrast, do not have biological causes per se. Inspired by the notion of a ‘para-natural kind’ – introduced by Roy Sorensen in 2011 – we claim that Mental Harms are the absence of a natural kind. This sounds complicated, but is actually pretty intuitive. To keep our explanation on point, assume that the mind is an optimally functioning information processing system, incredibly complex with various sub-systems. Call this the IPS-Kind. When that system stops working efficiently there might be various reasons or causes. Some will be biological – say, a brain lesion or some such, that restricts the functionality of the system. Some restricted functionality, however, may be attributed to causes of a different type. Imagine someone who becomes depressed due to a bereavement. The bereavement is hardly a biological cause of their depression, but it nevertheless results in sub-optimal functionality. In this sort of case our claim is that the IPS-Kind, or at least an element of it, is absent (i.e. it is now sub-optimal). This, we claim, is a mental harm.

Our aim in introducing this distinction is that how we conceptualise and classify psychiatric kinds is vital to how we approach, understand and treat the problems identified by psychiatry. Some Psychiatric Kinds cohere with the medical model of disease classification (i.e. diseases are construed as biological entities) with biological causes, whilst others do not. Both categories are quite properly of interest to contemporary psychiatry, as a branch of medical science. But distinguishing between them may have further implications for treatment choices – it may not be appropriate, for instance, to treat a mental harm pharmaceutically.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...