Skip to main content

Social Approaches to Delusions (2): Bayesian Psychiatry and the Social Focus of Delusions

Today's post is by Daniel Williams and Marcella Montagnese and it is the second in the series “Social Approaches to Delusions”. Daniel is an Early Career Research Fellow at Corpus Christi College, University of Cambridge, and Marcella is a doctoral student in the Department of Neuroimaging, Institute of Psychiatry, Psychology & Neuroscience, at King’s College London. Here Daniel and Marcella talk about their new paper “Bayesian Psychiatry and the Social Focus of Delusions”.

 

Daniel Williams
Daniel Williams



As with many other areas of psychology and philosophy, the study of delusions is taking a social turn. This has different manifestations. For example, in an extremely interesting article, Sam Wilkinson argues that the very attribution of delusional status to certain beliefs is wrapped up in social practices of folk-epistemic approval and disapproval. To call something a delusion, Wilkinson argues, is not to describe – or at least not only to describe – reality but to express a certain kind of disapproval at a violation of social-epistemic norms.

Other work focuses on the centrality of social cognition – and disturbances to social cognition – for understanding the kinds of beliefs that get characterised as delusions in psychiatry. This idea is central to Kengo Miyazono and Allesandro Salice’s fascinating “testimonial theory of delusion,” according to which a combination of testimonial isolation and testimonial discount play important and underappreciated roles in the formation, maintenance, and elaboration of delusions in schizophrenia. 

Vaughan Bell, Nichola Raihani, and – again – Sam Wilkinson similarly emphasise this reduced sensitivity to social context in their important manifesto for the importance of coalitional cognition for understanding delusions. Further, they speculate that evolved social mechanisms for managing social influence, affiliation, and strategic social behaviour are central for determining the overwhelmingly social themes of delusions, an idea that also plays a role in Joel and Ian Gold’s “social theory of delusions.” 


Marcella Montagnese
Marcella Montagnese



Our recent preprint, “Bayesian Psychiatry and the Social Focus of Delusions,” is a speculative attempt to connect this social turn in the study of delusions to influential work in computational psychiatry that draws on a conception of the brain as a hierarchically structured statistical inference mechanism.

As we note in our article, we are convinced of the importance and explanatory power of this research programme, which we refer to as “Bayesian psychiatry.” Not only is a conception of the brain as a predictive modelling engine utilising sophisticated forms of statistical inference increasingly well-established in cognitive and computational neuroscience, but this perspective offers a battery of important and illuminating conceptual, theoretical, and methodological tools for understanding the dysfunctions and aberrations that underlie psychiatric disorders.


Despite such attractions, we also argue that Bayesian psychiatry is sometimes tacitly aligned with a conception of the brain as a content-neutral, domain-general learning mechanism that is likely to obscure many of the distinctive ways in which the human mind can break down and malfunction. To illustrate this, we explore some of the most influential attempts to understand psychosis within this research programme, such as those that postulate aberrations in uncertainty-weighted prediction error minimisation and volatility estimation.


We argue that explanations of psychosis that rely on such domain-general learning differences are unlikely to be able to capture aspects of its highly domain specific phenomenology. For example, the overwhelmingly social themes of clinical delusions cluster in a tiny region of the vast space of possible themes that abnormal beliefs could represent, and it is difficult to see how generic dysfunctions in statistical inference could explain this. 

To address this, we suggest that Bayesian psychiatry might benefit from accommodating the evolved functional specialisations of the human brain. Of course, such functional specialisations are not realised in discrete self-contained anatomical modules at the macroscopic level of brain structures. Nevertheless, we speculate that Bayesian psychiatry will only be successful to the extent that it recognises that the brain’s statistical algorithms operate in the control centre of a unique primate that evolved to navigate a distinct world of opportunities and risks.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph