Skip to main content

Leaving the black box treatment of ignorance behind

Today's post is by Rik Peels. Rik is an Associate Professor in Philosophy and Religion & Theology at the Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam. He is currently leading a large research project funded by the European Research Council, on the epistemology and ethics of extreme beliefs.

He aims to synthesize empirical work with conceptual and normative approaches to fundamentalism, extremism, and conspiracy thinking.


 

For almost its entire history, philosophy has studied knowledge and understanding rather than ignorance. I see why: we seek to know and understand reality rather than be ignorant of it, at least for most things (privacy issues and the like may be an exception). And perhaps the tacit idea was that if we get a grip on knowledge and understanding, we thereby also have insight into the nature of ignorance, as ignorance is simply the lack of knowledge, or at least so it was thought. 

Even philosophical debates that appealed to ignorance, such as that about Socratic ignorance, negative theology, ignorance as an excuse, and white ignorance, were about the objects of ignorance (what we are ignorant of), and not about ignorance itself. As a result, ignorance has become a black box.

Rik Peels

In this book, I open that box and argue that all these tacit assumptions about ignorance are mistaken. Ignorance is not just the lack of knowledge: it is a highly complex, multi-layered notion that comes in numerous shapes and sizes. In a way ignorance is a notion far more complex than knowledge. To give an example: When one knows something, one has a justified true belief that a proposition is true (and some an anti-luck condition is met), or maybe something like knowledge-first epistemology is correct. 

But ignorance is much more varied: when one is ignorant, one can disbelieve a true proposition, one can suspend judgment on it, one can waver and not yet have adopted an attitude towards it, one can never have thought about it, or one may even lack the conceptual resources to consider it. 

Things get even more intriguing when we move to the realm of social epistemology: a group knows as a group when at least some members of the group have knowledge, particularly the operative members, but, remarkably, a group can be ignorant even when most or all members have knowledge. 

Imagine, for instance, that all twenty soldiers in an army unit witness an instance of sexual harassment. They are all individually convinced that what they see is morally wrong and in fact they know it. However, they do not dare to speak out and since nobody does, they think they are the only one in the group knowing that the misbehavior is morally wrong. They decide to keep it to themselves. As a consequence, the group carries on as it did before. It is not implausible to think that this is a case in which they all individually know of the moral wrongness of the act, yet as a group they are ignorant of that.

To better understand such cases, this book first develops an epistemology of ignorance and then applies it. By an ‘epistemology of ignorance’ I mean a theory that states what the nature of ignorance is (is it the lack of knowledge, the lack of understanding, or yet something else?), what kinds and varieties there are, what group ignorance is, and what it is for ignorance to come in degrees. I then show how this epistemology of ignorance provides crucial building blocks for solving various problems in philosophy and beyond. 

I address challenging questions regarding white ignorance, structural ignorance (intentionally keeping others ignorant), responsibility for ignorance, ignorance as an excuse, ignorance in education, and expressing one’s ignorance. 

In each case, we see that opening the black box of ignorance is fruitful. In fact, paradoxically, a full-blown epistemology of ignorance provides something that we have wanted all along: knowledge and understanding—but this time about ignorance itself.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph