Skip to main content

Inference and Epistemic Innocence

Will McNeill
This post is by Will McNeill, currently a teaching fellow at King's College London. He researches the epistemology of perception and recognition.

The main focus of PERFECT is on finding the epistemically valuable within mental pathologies of varying seriousness; of identifying pathological beliefs which are at least epistemically innocent. But in this post I want to bring our attention back to the cognitive processes of those with no serious cognitive impairments. It would not surprise me if many of our cognitive processes turn out to be epistemically innocent in a particularly direct way. They may turn out to be reliable, and to produce justified beliefs, while not being capable of explaining why the beliefs they produce are justified. Justified beliefs which are the direct products of such epistemically innocent processes are – I believe – foundational.

Suppose that we had good reason to think that someone was good at spotting emeralds. They tend to know, of emeralds, that they are emeralds. And they tend not to be fooled by the fakes. But suppose too that on other grounds we had good reason to think that the cognitive processes which generate their emerald beliefs relied in part on the thought that emeralds are grue.

On the one hand, we would have discovered something about the nature of their reliable capacity to spot emeralds. But on the other hand, we would not have produced any satisfying answer to the question of why they were warranted in their belief. At least, discovering that these deviant cognitive processes were at work would provide no more of an explanation of their warrant than the simple observation that they were de facto reliable at spotting emeralds.

The grue example is very obviously contrived. It is hard to imagine why our cognitive theory would have us positing grue generalizations. But think of those early ocean navigators. We have good reason to suppose that their heads were littered with false beliefs about the relationship between stars, sun, moon, and position. With imperfect tools they fashioned surprising reliability. Even if they had good warrant for holding some of these beliefs, and even if some of them were true, they are not in terms of their content sufficient to explain how the navigators knew where they were. Given how much falsity resided in the relevant cognitive processes their products could hardly be thought warranted on theoretical grounds. If the navigational beliefs such cognitive processes secured were good it was only because they were reliable. If there is knowledge here it is more intuitive than inferential.

Hopefully the thought is becoming clear. In both of the above cases, the actual cognitive processes at work appear epistemically innocent. They are not good in their own right. They do not manifest such theoretical virtues as parsimony, accuracy, or explanatory power. If they are good this is just because in the contexts in which they are employed they reliably secure the right results.

I see no reason to think that these kinds of epistemically innocent processes would be isolated or unusual. When we are engaged in modelling actual cognitive processes we want to be sensitive to the kinds of pressure that they are under. They need to be fast and frugal. Our models need to be evolutionarily plausible. But these criteria lend themselves to positing cognitive shortcuts, heuristics and other quick fixes. Positing such tricks might best describe the methods by which we reliably form true beliefs about our environment. But to the extent that such descriptions genuinely involve tricks, shortcuts, false generalizations, and biases they are surely epistemically unsatisfying. Or to put it another way, they are in a very direct way epistemically innocent. They may be reliable inferences. But they secure no distinctively inferential warrant.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...