Skip to main content

Religious Disagreement

Today's post is written by Helen de Cruz. Helen is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at Oxford Brookes University, UK. Her publications are in empirically-informed Philosophy of Cognitive Science, Philosophy of Religion, Social Epistemology, and Metaphilosophy. 

Helen's overarching research project is an investigation of how human engage in thinking about abstract domains such as Theology, Mathematics, and Science, what it means for limited, embodied beings like us to think about these topics, and what epistemic conclusions we can draw from this. Here, she introduces her new book "Religious Disagreement".



I find myself frequently in disagreement about religion with academic colleagues and friends and family. Given that I'm a philosopher of religion, this is not surprising. But my experiences are far from unique: religious disagreement is widespread even among quite homogeneous religious communities. There is disagreement both between and within religious communities.

While religious disagreement is common, it remains quite intractable to philosophers. Unlike idealized and clean cases, such as adding up and dividing the bill in a restaurant or visually discerning which horse finishes first in a race, religious disagreement is messy and tied up to many features of our identity. Moreover, religion also seems to rely on private evidence that is not easily shared, such as personal religious experiences. Because of this, it seems difficult to apply the notion of an epistemic peer to a religious dissenter.

I argue in my brief monograph “Religious Disagreement” that disagreement presents a form of higher-order evidence even if we cannot ascertain that our interlocutor is an exact epistemic peer or epistemic superior.

I present a conciliationist point of view: I argue that the religious beliefs of others amount to evidence that should lead us to at the very least evaluate, and sometimes alter, our religious views.

This book does not provide a comprehensive survey of religious disagreement in all its different forms. Rather, I examine what practical conclusions we can draw in the face of particular forms of religious disagreement. These include disagreement with a purported peer (chapter 1), with possible other selves, who were raised in a different religious environment (chapter 2), and with our former self, before a religious conversion (chapter 3).

I also look at the epistemic significance of religious agreement, and how we should evaluate its evidential value (chapter 4). Chapter 5 looks at what we can learn from disagreement among religious experts. Finally, chapter 6 explores why philosophy matters for religious disagreement among non-philosophers, particularly in the public sphere.

In keeping with the topic of this book, I structured each chapter (except the introductory and concluding chapter) around a central figure who has done major conceptual work within a given religious tradition: al-Ghazālī (chapter 2), Augustine (chapter 3), Calvin (chapter 4), and Maimonides (chapter 5).

For example, Chapter 2 on irrelevant influences and religious disagreement focuses on al-Ghazālī, a Medieval Muslim theologian who lived in what is now Iran. He worried about religious diversity and the threat it poses to the justification of his own religious beliefs. He observed that Muslim children always grow up to be Muslims, Jewish children into Jewish adults, and Christian children into Christian adults. He also thought that Aristotelian philosophers too easily and readily accepted the tradition they were taught in. But how could he be sure that his own religious and philosophical beliefs were true, given the large influence of factors beyond his control?

Al-Ghazālī’s initial response to this worry was that he could, as a philosopher, critically reflect on his ideas so that testimony did not exert this negative influence: “the bonds of mere authority (taqlīd) ceased to hold me and inherited beliefs lost their grip upon me”. But this seems unlikely, as I have found in earlier experimental philosophical work that philosophers of religion — who carefully reflect on religious views — are still very much influenced by factors such as their education and upbringing.

His second response, the cultivation of religious (Sufi) practices to help overcome cognitive limitations, seems more promising. However, mystical experience tends to vary with the religious traditions in which they occur, so it is not clear that knowledge based on this would escape the arbitrariness objection. It is no coincidence that al-Ghazālī had mystical experiences that support Islam, while Teresa of Ávila had experiences that were in line with Catholicism. 

In the concluding chapter, I argue that philosophy of religion matters, or should matter, to disagreements in the public sphere. Philosophers of religion often provide expert versions of ordinary religious disagreements, such as about the problem of evil or the epistemic significance of religious revelation (this not the case for all discussions in the philosophy of religion, but an important subset).

I’m inclined to think (as authors such as Gary Gutting and W.V.O. Quine have defended earlier) that there is nothing special about philosophy. Philosophers don't seem to have access to a special fount of intuitions, as their intuitions seem to be subject to the same kinds of framing effects as those of non-philosophers.

However, I have argued earlier that philosophers are experts of some sort: they can come up with good stories and scenarios that elicit intuitions, and they carefully look at objections and support for arguments. The fact that there is nothing inherently philosophical about philosophy is a cause for optimism.

If philosophers draw on the same sorts of reasoning and resources as ordinary people (e.g., the empirical evidence for a claim, the internal coherence for a claim) this also means that philosophical knowledge does not require any special defence or justification. And it also means that philosophers of religion have thought through problems that beset the ordinary person in their more reflective moments, such as whether an omnibenevolent God can exist in the face of devastating evil?

Philosophers of religion are not immune to irrelevant influences. But this is not a problem, as I argue we can let diversity work. Given the wide diversity of religious beliefs across cultures, it is important that philosophers of religion engage with a wide range of traditions, not just those found in Christianity in western cultures.

For this reason, I have, for example, recently obtained funds from the APA’s diversity and inclusiveness fund to sponsor a competition at the Journal of Analytic Theology (where I am co-editor) for best paper from an underrepresented theological tradition. Ultimately, I think that intellectual diversity and thoughtful debate — both within philosophy and the wider public sphere — can help communities inside and outside of philosophy to obtain more justified religious beliefs.



Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph