Skip to main content

The Rise of Polarization: Affects, Politics, and Philosophy

This post is by Manuel Almagro (University of Valencia). Here he presents his new book, The Rise of Polarization (Routledge 2025).


Book cover



When I was young, I used to think that doing things you don’t like or that don’t represent you was always wrong. I also believed that all politicians were cut from the same cloth. If asked, I could give reasons for those beliefs. But I hadn’t arrived at them by carefully considering arguments or evidence; they just felt perfectly natural and obviously true, given my experiences and environment at the time.

Today, I wouldn’t hold such beliefs. Is that because I’ve been exposed to arguments against them? Not really. I’ve changed through living, talking, and sharing experiences with people who see things differently. Friction with others, especially those who care about us, is essential for reflecting on what’s right, how we should live, and what we should believe. The experiences I’ve gone through have made me more receptive to the pull of certain narratives I once would have dismissed.

Since the late 2000s, however, many contemporary democracies have increasingly faced something that challenges the positive consequences of having friction with others, at least in the political domain. Public opinion has become sharply divided, and friction with “the other side” rarely feels productive. Even people we care about have become “the others.” In 2018, I went to my parents’ house for a family meeting and couldn’t believe what some of my relatives were saying on certain political issues. They were suddenly “the others.”

The most widely accepted explanation of what’s happening in contemporary democracies holds that societies have become polarized—specifically, affectively polarized. The standard view emphasizes two key factors: partisanship and emotions. Simply put, citizens, typically “the others”, are increasingly attached to particular political identities, which makes them to have positive feelings toward the in-group and negative feelings toward the out-group.

This view favors a diagnosis according to which people, usually “the others”, are epistemically and cognitively deficient: they no longer think critically or base their political views on arguments and evidence. They don’t even care about truth. Citizens, the story goes, just want their side to win.


Manuel Almagro


It’s easy to get swept up in that story. In 2018, I felt that some of my relatives, like nearly half the population, were shielded against reason. Their views didn’t seem to be based on arguments. I had forgotten that I didn’t need arguments to believe that doing things you don’t like is wrong, or that all politicians are the same, just as I didn’t need them to stop believing such things. How do others become “the others”? Are arguments and evidence relevant for that?

The book argues that both the two-dimensional view of affective polarization and the diagnosis it favors are mistaken. Citizens are not epistemically deficient, and the role that arguments and evidence play, or are assumed to play, in shaping political beliefs is often idealized. To make this case, the book explores three key issues: the contingent origins of many of our beliefs, the influence of divisive narratives, and the distinction between abstract and concrete judgments.

More specifically, it argues that affective polarization exploits ordinary belief-forming mechanisms. It involves the mainstreaming of certain ideas, framed within divisive narratives and promoted by political actors, that people embrace with high credence in the abstract because it is rational for them to do so. This way of conceiving affective polarization has important implications for detecting and intervening in polarization processes.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...