Skip to main content

Epistemic Urgency: a Positive Dimension to Reasoning Biases in Schizophrenia?

Gregory Yates
I am a Masters student in Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science at the University of Birmingham. My research interests here are centred on the experiences of patients diagnosed with schizophrenia. I am also involved with the CogWatch project at Birmingham, a European funded research initiative aiming to enhance the rehabilitation of patients suffering from neurological disorders. Much of my theoretical and practical work, then, concerns cognitions seen as ‘imperfect’!

An article posted to Imperfect Cognitions in May explored the often-overlooked positive-psychological qualities or ‘secondary gains’ (Graham, 2013) associated with manic-depressive illness. I would like to consider here whether anything similar can be found in psychotic disorders – namely, schizophrenia.
 
I will evaluate for now just one trait common to schizophrenia patients worth special consideration from an epistemic point of view. I will refer to this trait as epistemic urgency.
Epistemic urgency describes the tendency of schizophrenia patients to exhibit reasoning biases that cause them to “jump to conclusions” in response to ordinary events, and as a result form delusional beliefs. That conversation that ends abruptly when you walk into the room? A scheme to poison you, quickly hushed up. That weatherman that wears a green tie on Thursdays? He’s broadcasting a secret code, for your eyes only.
What makes these beliefs irrational is their urgency, their failure to satisfy conventional evidence thresholds for epistemic rationality prior to endorsement (see Bortolotti, 2010). 

What makes these beliefs delusional, and thus cause for psychiatric intervention, is their underlying bias, and the health risks associated with leaving this bias to run its course (Larson et al., 2010). These risks, however, appear to be context-dependent. Certain experimental paradigms have demonstrated that there are contexts in which schizophrenia patients perform better as a direct result of this epistemic urgency.
A clear example of this in action can be found in a popular study carried out by Baruch, Hemsley, and Gray (1988). This study investigated latent inhibition (LI) in schizophrenia. LI describes the following effect: if a stimulus is repeatedly presented to an organism in absence of reinforcement then presented with reinforcement of some kind, the organism will learn the stimulus/reinforcement association slower than an organism exposed only to the reinforced stimulus. Simply, LI is this: why bother to learn information repeatedly experienced as redundant?
It has been hypothesised that LI is disrupted in schizophrenia (Hemsley,1991). Schizophrenia patients frequently report experiences of perceptual inundation; their ‘stream’ of consciousness disturbed, they find themselves unable to use stored memories to allocate attentional resources and, consequently, experience all stimuli as novel (Lubow et al., 1982). That disrupted LI underlies this is indicated by Baruch et al.’s study, which found that acute schizophrenia patients, in spite of pre-exposure to a stimulus, continue to attend to it, and thus score higher than controls on measures of learning (Baruch, Hemsley & Gray, 1988). 
Baruch et al.’s study provides a missing link between perceptual inundation and epistemic urgency. Schizophrenia patients, unable to draw on past experiences of ‘redundant’ stimuli, attribute undue importance to these stimuli.
 
Their study also sheds some light on the positive dimension to epistemic urgency. Many tasks demand “fresh” experiences of ordinary information, particularly when events are not straightforwardly predictable (Maher, 1974). A popular example of this is crime scene investigation, which often requires careful attention to superficially ‘irrelevant’ information (Technical Working Group on Crime Scene Investigation, 2000). A more controversial example is the production of art. In any case, epistemic urgency can be viewed as a positive trait to schizophrenia. Whether it can be viewed as a ‘secondary gain’ to the same extent as the positive traits described in manic depressive illness is something to be decided on a case-by-case basis. 

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph