Skip to main content

Interview with Martin Davies: Delusions (Part 2)

Martin Davies
This is the second part of an interview with Professor Martin Davies on delusions. You can read the first part of the interview here.


LB: Presentations of the two-factor account of delusion formation usually begin with two questions. The first question is about where the content of the delusion came from and the second is about the adoption or persistence of the belief. The two factors are supposed to provide answers to these two questions. But it sounds as if you are distinguishing a question about adoption from a question about persistence (or maintenance). If there are more than two questions to be answered, will an explanation of a delusion have to appeal to more than two factors?

MKD: Thank you for raising this issue of the relationship between questions and factors. It is quite important for understanding the two-factor framework. Questions about the aetiology of a delusion can be multiplied and, correspondingly, explanations of a delusion can be increasingly detailed, appealing to more than two ‘factors’ in the ordinary sense of that term. But, crucially, factors in the sense relevant to the two-factor framework are not just elements in an explanation. They are, specifically, pathologies or departures from normality, such as neuropsychological deficits.

You are right to say that I want to distinguish between a question about adoption of the delusional belief and a question about the belief’s persistence. If we are going to say something substantive about the nature of the second factor then we need to be clear about the role of the second factor. Where, in the total story of the aetiology of a delusion, does it figure? So, along with the first question about the source of the delusional idea or hypothesis, there should be the adoption question, ‘Why is the delusional hypothesis adopted as a belief?’, and the persistence question, ‘Why does that belief, once adopted, persist; why is it not subsequently rejected?’.

I think it is widely agreed that explaining a delusion requires answers to all three of these questions. But that does not settle the issue whether more than two factors are required in total. Perhaps one or other of the adoption and persistence questions can be answered without appeal to a departure from normality. For example, Max Coltheart, Peter Menzies and John Sutton (2010) argued, using Capgras delusion as their example, that no second departure from normality is required to answer the adoption question, but that a second factor is required to answer the persistence question.

Andy Egan and I (2013) argued for a similar view, at least for some cases of delusion. In response to Coltheart and colleagues (2010), Ryan McKay (2012) argued that a second factor is required to answer the adoption question, but that no third departure from normality is required to answer the persistence question. Another possibility is that both questions can be answered by appeal to the same departure from normality.

So it is certainly possible that three questions might be answered without appealing to more than two factors. But it is also possible that, in some or all cases of delusion, answering the adoption and persistence questions might require appeal to two different departures from normality – so that three factors would figure in the overall explanation of the delusion (consistent with the at-least-two-factor theory, but not with the exactly-two-factor theory).

LB: Do you think there are any additional questions that might have to be answered by appeal to an additional factor?

MKD: Perhaps some recent work by Matthew Parrott (summarised here) suggests that there might be. We can think of the process of hypothesis evaluation as comparing the merits of a small number of competing explanatory hypotheses – a short list of live candidates. But then, it might be said, some hypotheses are so bizarre or so implausible that, normatively, they should not be considered as live candidates at all. For example, Parrott (in press) has proposed that an explanatory hypothesis is not worth considering seriously if it is already excluded by what one knows; that is, if it is ‘epistemically impossible’. So, alongside the adoption and persistence questions, the live candidate question arises: Why is the delusional hypothesis – even if it comes to the patient’s mind – not excluded at the very outset on the grounds that it is not a live candidate?

Even if the delusional hypothesis comes to the patient’s mind as a result of the anomalous experience (explained by the first factor), there are three distinct opportunities to reject it: it could be excluded from the short list at the outset; it could be rejected in a process of hypothesis evaluation on the grounds that there are stronger candidates on the short list; or it could be rejected in a process of post-adoption belief evaluation. In a case of delusion, how many departures from normality are required to explain this threefold failure of rejection? The two-factor theorist (specifically, the exactly-two-factor theorist) must answer, ‘Just one’.


The third part of this interview with Martin Davies will be published next Thursday.


References

Coltheart, M., Menzies, P. and Sutton, J. 2010: Abductive inference and delusional belief. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 15, 261–87.

Davies, M. and Egan, A. 2013: Delusion, cognitive approaches: Bayesian inference and compartmentalisation. In K.W.M. Fulford, M. Davies, R.G.T. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini and T. Thornton (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 689–727.

McKay, R. 2012: Delusional inference. Mind & Language, 27, 330–55.

Parrott, M. in press: Bayesian models, delusional beliefs, and epistemic possibilities. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph