Skip to main content

Lying, Truth, and Truthfulness

Stephen Wright
I'm Stephen Wright, a lecturer at the University of Oxford. I completed my PhD at the University of Sheffield in 2014, I mainly work on issues in epistemology and the philosophy of language. Whilst my research is primarily in the epistemology of testimony, I have recently been thinking about philosophical issues concerning lying, in preparing a piece for the forthcoming Oxford Handbook of Lying edited by Jörg Meibauer.

One of the questions at the centre of philosophical investigations into lying concerns what exactly lying is. In particular, I have been looking at the question of whether lying involves saying something that is untrue, or something that is untruthful. Put another way, the question is whether what I say can be a lie only if it is false, or if it merely seems to me that it is false.

Those that defend that idea that lying involves saying something untrue endorse the following claim:

(1) S’s statement that p is a lie only if p is false.

Thomas Carson (2010) endorses (1). According to Carson, someone’s statement is a lie only if it is false. The evidence for this comes from the observation that we cannot charge someone with lying once we find out that what she said was true. If you tell me that the portrait in the hall has been taken away and I accuse you of lying, it looks as though, when we go and check and find out that the portrait in the hall has in fact been taken away, I ought to retract my accusation.

Accounts that take lying to be a matter of saying something untruthful, rather than untrue, such as the recent one offered by Jennifer Saul (2012) endorse the following in place of (1):

(2) S’s statement that p is a lie only if S believes that p is false.

The idea is that what matters is not so much the truth or falsity of the speaker’s statement, so much as whether or not the speaker believes it to be true. For example, if I am attempting to conceal a fugitive in my house and I tell you that there is nobody hiding in my house, it seems that my statement is still a lie even if the fugitive has in fact escaped without me knowing it.

Of course, since (1) and (2) respectively only purport to state necessary conditions on lying, one might perfectly well endorse them both—they do not rule one another out. Indeed, this is Carson’s position. But many find (1) unintuitive for the reason given in the previous paragraph and I think there’s an intuitive reason to be suspicious of (2) as well.

The reason comes from a locus classicus in the literature concerning lying—Chisholm and Feehan’s (1977) discussion. Suppose that I tell you that there are robbers in the road. Chisholm and Feehan distinguish between two cases:

(i) I believe that there are no robbers in the road.

(ii) I believe that there ‘there are robbers in the road’ is false.

The idea is that, in (i) I believe the negation of what I say, whereas in (ii) I believe a ‘second-level’ about the proposition ‘there are robbers in the road’ which requires the concept of being false as applied to sentences.

Insofar as we can distinguish between (i) and (ii), I suggest that this distinction shows that we should not think that lying involves saying something that you believe to be false. It seems that you could perfectly well lie to somebody by saying the negation of something that you believe. If I believe that there are robbers in the road and I tell you that there are no robbers in the road, that would seem (to me) to be sufficiently untruthful to count as a lie.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph