Skip to main content

On Madness: Understanding the Psychotic Mind

Today’s post is by Richard Gipps, clinical psychologist and philosopher. Richard’s psychotherapy practice is in Oxford, UK, where he also teaches some philosophy. Along with Michael Lacewing he edited The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychoanalysis (2019). 

Gipps' philosophical interests concern the nature of psychotherapeutic action, psychotic thought, and the significance of love and moral virtue for mental health. Today he writes about his new book On Madness: Understanding the Psychotic Mind (Bloomsbury 2022).




How is madness to be met with? What kind of recognition can we show, and justice can we do, to its sufferer? On hearing his fragmented and delusional discourse we’re troubled by it - not so much because we fear what he'll say or do, but because now, trying to empathically relate to them, our minds judder and the ground slips out from under our feet. On the one hand: here’s a deeply troubled human being; on the other, our mustering of ordinary humane sense-making is now severely challenged.

Confronted by this challenge, those tasked with helping the mentally ill can find themselves tempted by what On Madness describes as two characteristic evasions. One, which most bedevils biomedical psychiatry, takes refuge in the thought that, with the person in their psychosis, what we find is not so much a suffering, meaning-responsive, human being, but a currently broken mechanism. ‘Nothing to see here; medicate, watch and wait until the human subject returns to the scene’ becomes the motto. 

Such an approach voids the task of humanly relating to the psychotic subject in a more than paternalistic manner. The second, rather more characteristic of much clinical psychology, urges that what looks like broken meaning is but a surface appearance to be penetrated. ‘Discard your prejudices about madness and instead try to reach the sense-making mind behind the symptoms’ is this approach’s tagline; its corollary intellectual aim is the development of reason-retrieving resources which, when held in mind in the clinic, will enable empathic engagement to be reestablished.

Such approaches effectively privilege the significance of rationality for humane intelligibility. Either reason’s absence is taken as an invitation to adopt a merely paternalistic stance, or we’re invited to restore human contact through cleverly discerning reason’s now hidden form. On Madness takes a different tack. It asks how we may instead bear with and honour someone in her rational brokenness by taking it as an index of her overwhelm. 


Richard Gipps


The tack taken is similar to that of apophatic (or ‘negative’) theology: we come to understand God’s reality by understanding how even our most superlative attributions to Him inexorably fail to do Him justice. So too, goes the suggestion, can we come to understand the psychotic subject when we see how even our most ingenious attempts to retrieve rational order here fail to do justice to the shame, objectless dread, and brokenness which she suffers.

None of this is to say that nothing properly called understanding may be had of this subject. In truth, certain forms of intelligibility - causal explanations, phenomenological characterisations, psychodynamic motivational understanding, so-called ‘symbolic’ meaning - become all the more relevant, and sometimes only possible, once we’ve already been turned away at reason’s door. 

On Madness separates out the distinct logical forms of these modes of understanding, showing how some may yet be available whilst others are thwarted; spells out the implications of its ‘apophatic’ approach for understanding what it is to be in one’s own world (the ‘waking dream’ or ‘lost reality-testing’ of psychosis); and carefully articulates the character of delusional, confusional, and hallucinatory thought and experience. 

The book ends by considering the question of psychiatric judgement. Ought one to make one’s judgements of the psychotic subject’s delusionality and disordered thought accountable by evaluating them according to general criteria? Or might this in truth itself be an evasion of the responsibility to embody psychiatric discernment within oneself?

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph