Skip to main content

Challenges in inpatient psychiatric settings

Here Martino Belvederi Murri (University of Ferrara) discusses research on epistemic justice and dignity for people with psychosis. A version of this post appeared on the EPIC blog in July 2024.


Martino Belvederi Murri


Individuals experiencing acute psychosis in inpatient psychiatric settings face unique challenges. Consider the case of Jake, a student who is struggling between familial conflicts and economic difficulties, as well as choices related to his life career. Auditory hallucinations may take the form of “voices” that comment on his everyday actions, and may lead Jake to think that people spy on him with malevolent intent. These symptoms can lead to angst and withdrawal from social activities, possibly culminating into severe anxiety and agitation.

The grave societal stigma that is attached to mental illness exacerbates feelings of isolation and diminishes help-seeking. The promotion of patient empowerment is a key component of recovery, and is increasingly seen as a duty of healthcare providers (Larkin and Hutton 2017). People like Jake desire respect and understanding by healthcare providers, need clear and empathetic communication, and want genuine involvement in decision-making (Stovell et al. 2016). Core themes in inpatient treatment are those of powerlessness, quality of care environment, relationship to staff, psychological and physical impact of involuntary treatment, and coercive practices.

Mood and morale

The experience of psychosis in itself and coercive treatment might constitute a “double hit” for the individual’s sense of self-worth, mood, hope, morale. Enhanced insight into one’s mental health is a desirable condition, but can paradoxically lead to adverse outcomes, a phenomenon often referred to as the “insight paradox” (Lysaker, Roe and Yanos 2007Belvederi Murri et al. 2016). 

This paradox suggests that insight can also lead to increased distress and depression: patients who gain a clear awareness of their psychosis often experience a profound sense of loss and sadness over their perceived decline in personal and social identity. It is particularly evident among people who hold self-stigmatizing beliefs. 

Demoralization may also manifest in patients with chronic psychotic illnesses, but also affective disorders, as loss of hope after a lifetime of struggling with an illness (Grassi et al. 2020) and may be expressed as reduced quality of life. As patients become more cognizant of how they are perceived and treated by others due to their illness, this can exacerbate feelings of hopelessness and low self-worth. However, the effect is tempered by better relationship with the carers. 

On one hand, insight can empower patients, allowing for better self-management and informed decision-making; on the other, it can heighten awareness of stigma, the possible chronicity of their condition, and the impact on their life goals, thereby contributing to depressive symptoms or even suicide (Berardelli et al. 2021). Addressing the insight paradox in treatment planning requires fostering an environment that promotes insight while simultaneously providing robust emotional support and therapeutic interventions to mitigate the distressing impact of such insights. 


Hearing voices


Psychosis and epistemic injustice

The concept of epistemic injustice is particularly relevant both for the consequences of psychosis (as a clinical phenomenon) and for the experience of treatment. Individuals with psychosis often find themselves at the intersection of testimonial and hermeneutic injustices, where their capacity to know and communicate their experiences is unfairly discounted due to the nature of the illness and to the internal or external stigmatization of their condition (Smyth 2021Kidd, Spencer and Carel 2022).

Testimonial injustice may occur when an individual's account of their experiences is disregarded or deemed unreliable, not because of the content of their testimony but because of prejudicial beliefs about their capacity to know (‘identity-prejudicial’ stereotype). For individuals with psychosis, this form of injustice is all too common, as the hallmark symptoms of their condition—delusions and hallucinations—are often dismissed as mere artefacts of their illness, rather than expressions of lived reality. 

Patients with psychosis are judged not to have capacity and are considered completely unreliable in all aspects of their testimony, not just in regard to the content of a particular delusion or hallucination. But psychosis does not necessarily invade all realms of mental functioning and in many instances, patients may hold reliable accounts of a large proportion of their reality and experience. 

The generic, “by default”, dismissal of the whole testimony of people with psychosis not only silences their voices but also impedes their recovery by fostering feelings of isolation, alienation from the healthcare system and society at large (Lysaker and Lysaker 2010). 

It could be argued that a person experiencing psychosis does also risk to commit testimonial injustice on themselves, by judging the self-experience of the world less reliable than it is, and by developing what is called self- or internalized stigma, which is particularly relevant for subsequent loss of self-esteem (Fernández et al. 2023).


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...