Skip to main content

“I’m Not Hungry:” Bodily Representations and Bodily Experiences in Anorexia Nervosa

Today's post is by Mara Floris on her recent paper "“I’m Not Hungry:” Bodily Representations and Bodily Experiences in Anorexia Nervosa" (Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2024).

Anorexia Nervosa (AN) is a severe psychiatric disorder characterized by an intense fear of gaining weight, leading to extreme food restriction and a distorted perception of one’s own body. In our paper, we explore how individuals with AN experience significant alterations in two primary domains: bodily representations and bodily experiences.

Mara Floris

Bodily Representations and Perceptual Distortions
Bodily representations refer to the cognitive and perceptual processes that help us perceive and understand our body’s size, shape, and function. In individuals with AN, these representations are often distorted, leading to body image disturbances. These disturbances manifest as an overestimation of body size—patients with AN often perceive themselves as larger than they are. This misperception is not limited to their body alone but extends to how they view food, seeing it as more substantial than it is. We also discuss the potential cognitive factors influencing these perceptual distortions, positing that they might serve as a defense mechanism aimed at reinforcing the desire to maintain or reduce body weight.

Bodily Experiences and Interoceptive Awareness
In addition to altered bodily representations, individuals with AN experience significant changes in bodily awareness and interoceptive sensitivity—how they perceive internal bodily signals such as hunger, fullness, and pain. These individuals often report a heightened sense of being "full" after consuming minimal amounts of food and experience difficulty recognizing and interpreting hunger signals. This altered interoceptive awareness might contribute to the suppression of appetite and reinforce restrictive eating behaviors. Moreover, there is a connection between interoceptive deficits and emotional dysregulation in AN, as difficulties in identifying internal states may impair emotional processing and regulation.

Cognitive Penetrability of Perception (CPP)
Our paper also delves into the philosophical debate on the Cognitive Penetrability of Perception (CPP), which posits that our beliefs, desires, and mental states can influence how we perceive sensory information. We propose that the perceptual distortions seen in AN could provide empirical evidence for CPP. For instance, the belief that "eating will make me fat" could directly impact how individuals with AN perceive their body size and the size of food portions. This interplay between cognition and perception suggests that higher-order cognitive processes might penetrate perceptual experiences in individuals with AN, leading to altered bodily representations and experiences.

Implications and Future Directions
Understanding these altered perceptions and experiences is crucial for developing more effective interventions for AN. By recognizing that these distortions are not merely cognitive or emotional but are rooted in perceptual experiences, clinicians can better tailor their approaches to address these core psychopathological features. Future research should continue to explore the multisensory nature of body perception in AN and investigate how cognitive processes influence these perceptions. Additionally, there is a need for more studies on the temporal onset of these distortions to better understand whether they precede or are a consequence of the development of AN.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. TrĆ©moliĆØre (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...