Skip to main content

On the rationality of thought-insertion judgements

Today’s post is contributed by Víctor Verdejo. He is a philosopher of language and mind who has recently published the article “On the rationality of thought-insertion judgments”, now featuring in a special collection on delusions in Philosophical Psychology. Víctor Verdejo is currently a Ramón y Cajal fellow at Pompeu Fabra University in Barcelona, and a member of Logos Research Group.


Víctor Verdejo

We often think of delusional experience as not particularly revealing with respect to a subject’s rationality. In this paper, I explore a different—some might say daring—approach: what if delusional experience were to illuminate the rational grounds associated with our judgments and concepts? In this work, I focus on the experience of thought-insertion and the first-person concept.

Consider what I term the “rationality hypothesis”: this hypothesis holds that when subjects with schizophrenia report thought insertion, they may be expressing fully rational judgments about the ownership of their thoughts. These subjects report feeling as though thoughts they can introspect are not their own. This seems puzzling and may lead to questioning whether individuals with such experiences can really understand or intelligibly explain their own reports and judgments. 

By contrast, the rationality hypothesis considers the reports as not just comprehensible—as John Campbell and others have suggested in other work—but also as reflecting the basic structure of one’s rational grounds for self-ascriptions of thought. This approach brings out a deeper sense in which subjects undergoing the experience can be considered to be rational. In doing so, it not only makes sense of the patients’ capacity for rational thought—beyond their mental condition—but also offers key insights into the nature of thought insertion and the first person.

Two insights in particular arise from the rationality hypothesis. First, from this angle the reports of thought insertion can be seen as evidence that our judgments about whether we own a thought—whether the thought is truly ours—depend more on our agentive awareness than on our introspective awareness of that thought. In other words, thought-insertion reports show that, in order to rationally determine whether a thought is ours, we rely first and foremost on whether we have the experience of having caused or controlled that thought (agency awareness) rather than simply on whether we are aware of it introspectively (introspective awareness). Interestingly, this first insight aligns with mainstream theories about how thought insertion operates on both a personal and mechanistic level. 

The second key insight provided by the rationality hypothesis concerns the use of the first-person pronoun and the associated first-person concept. Suppose that—following the hypothesis—it is fully rational under certain circumstances to judge that an introspectively accessible thought is not our own. It just seems to follow that there are different kinds of awareness—ways or perspectives—I can exploit when considering the relevant uses of the first person (other applications of this basic idea can be found in Verdejo 2018, 2021, 2023). 

The presumption is that, when considering our thoughts, a full-fledged first-person perspective towards them is only available when agency awareness is also present. This is thus the kind of awareness that seems most fundamentally involved in fixing the referent of the first-person concept. Bluntly put, and pace an illustrious Cartesian tradition, when we refer to ourselves with “I” in thought self-ascription, we take ourselves to be fundamentally the agents, and not the introspectors of our thoughts.

These insights have both ethical and theoretical drives. Ethically, the rationality hypothesis respects the cognitive capabilities of individuals experiencing thought insertion, treating their experiences as genuine and valuable sources for understanding the mind and rationality. Theoretically, it highlights the complexity of self-awareness in ways that align with available reports and accounts, challenging the traditional idea that introspective awareness is the essential rational basis for establishing ownership of one’s thoughts. 


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...