Skip to main content

Folk Intuitions about Free Will: Falure to Understand Determinism and Motivated Cognition

Today's post is by Kiichi Inarimori (Hokkaido University) on his recent paper "Folk Intuitions About Free Will and Moral Responsibility: Evaluating the Combined Effects of Misunderstandings About Determinism and Motivated Cognition" (Cognitive Science 2024), co-authored with Yusuke Haruki (The University of Tokyo) and Kengo Miyazono (Hokkaido University).

Kiichi Inarimori
Philosophers have long debated whether free will—a prerequisite for moral responsibility—is compatible with determinism. Central to these discussions are the intuitions people form when considering moral responsibility in hypothetical scenarios.

Yusuke Haruki
With the rise of experimental philosophy, numerous studies have explored folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Some experiments suggest that people tend toward “compatibilism,” the view that free will and determinism can coexist, especially in concrete cases of wrongdoing. Others suggest a lean toward “incompatibilism,” the view that free will is impossible in a deterministic world.

Kengo Miyazono
Why do these intuitions vary so much? One possible explanation lies in misunderstandings of determinism. It has been shown that many people mistakenly equate causal determination with bypassing—the idea that mental states like desires and beliefs have no causal role in actions. It is also suggested that many people fail to grasp that determinism excludes alternative possibilities (intrusion). These misunderstandings can influence responses: bypassing is associated with increased incompatibilist responses, while intrusion tends to increase compatibilist responses. Another possible explanation is motivated cognition. Studies by Cory Clark and colleagues suggest that attributions of free will and responsibility may be influenced by a desire to hold wrongdoers accountable.

Our recent study, published in Cognitive Science, aimed to uncover why people exhibit such divergent intuitions. We focused on two key factors: misunderstandings about determinism and the desire to punish wrongdoers, which is hypothesized to be linked with compatibilist responses.

To investigate these effects, we conducted a large-scale experiment with over 1,000 participants in Japan. Participants were presented with scenarios describing deterministic worlds and asked to evaluate whether a person committing a morally significant act (like murder) acted of their own free will and whether they should be held morally responsible.

A unique feature of our study was the use of new materials designed to improve comprehension of determinism. For instance, we created video explanations contrasting a deterministic universe with a non-deterministic one, alongside traditional text-based descriptions. We also assessed participants’ understanding of determinism, measuring their susceptibility to bypassing and intrusion. In addition, participants were asked to report their desire to punish the wrongdoer in each scenario.

Our findings were illuminating. While misunderstandings about determinism—especially bypassing—were common, they only partially explained participants’ responses. Intrusion effects, in particular, were minimal, as most participants correctly understood that determinism excludes alternative possibilities. A more significant predictor of moral responsibility attributions was participants’ retributive desires. Those with stronger desires to punish wrongdoers were significantly more likely to attribute free will and moral responsibility—even when they conflated causal determination with bypassing.

These results suggest that intuitions about free will and moral responsibility are more malleable than previously assumed. People appear to hold both compatibilist and incompatibilist intuitions, and motivational factors, such as a desire for punishment, play a crucial role in shaping which intuition dominates. For philosophers, this raises challenging questions about the traditional dichotomy between compatibilism and incompatibilism.

However, our study did not establish a causal relationship between retributive desire and responsibility attribution, even though the association was clear. Additionally, we found significant scenario effects: participants’ responses depended on how deterministic scenarios were presented. These findings highlight the complexity of folk intuitions and suggest that understanding their formation requires careful attention to both cognitive and emotional factors.

While our study is just one step toward unpacking these dynamics, it underscores the need for further research across diverse contexts and cultures. By better understanding these mechanisms, we can gain deeper insights into how people navigate fundamental questions about free will and responsibility.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...