Skip to main content

Rational People's Irrational Beliefs

This post is by Chenwei Nie (University of Warwick). In this post, Chenwei discusses a proposal detailed in his new chapter, "Why rational people obstinately hold onto irrational beliefs: A new approach", to appear in a book entitled Epistemic Dilemmas and Epistemic Normativity (Routledge).


Chenwei Nie

In the middle of this brutal summer, with scorching heatwaves across Europe, Asia, and North America, it is poignant that so many believe that climate change is not real. Nearly 15% of Americans believe it is not real (Gounaridis & Newell, 2024), and among the members of the 118th US Congress, almost a quarter share this belief, who are all Republicans (So, 2024). Even more alarming, climate change denial is just one example in a much broader, unsettling set of irrational beliefs, including but not limited to cases of superstitious, religious, political, and conspiratorial beliefs. The burning question is: Why do people obstinately hold onto irrational beliefs in the face of counterevidence?

When a belief fails to be sensitive to evidence as it should and is epistemically irrational (Bortolotti, 2010), it is likely influenced by non-evidential factors that do not bear on the truth of the belief. In the case of climate denial, the non-evidential factors may include the denier’s anxiety over the catastrophic implications of climate change, her fondness for Trump whom she may take to be a climate denier as well, and her practical consideration that the belief solidifies her identity as a proud Republican. What is less clear is how exactly non-evidential factors contribute to the development of irrational beliefs.

Existing approaches often assume that non-evidential factors either distort the way the person collects and evaluates independent evidence or are taken by the person as evidence for her belief (Schleifer McCormick, 2020; Glüer & Wikforss, 2022; Simion, 2024; Flores, forthcoming). 


Existing approaches


While acknowledging that these irrational cases can occur, my chapter proposes a new approach that does not presuppose such irrationalities and allows for the possibility that the person is clear-eyed about the conflict between her belief and independent evidence. According to this new approach, non-evidential factors may contribute to the formation and maintenance of a distinctive kind of seeming experience (also referred to as appearance, intuition, or impression). 

The climate denier’s anxiety over the catastrophic implications of climate change, her fondness for Trump, and her practical consideration may give rise to a very strong seeming that climate change is not real. A seeming itself is not a belief (Pryor, 2000; Huemer, 2001; Tucker, 2013; McCain & Moretti, 2021; McAllister, 2023). But a strong seeming can, in various ways and degrees, compel belief. Specifically, a strong seeming that p may causally incline the person to believe that p (Nie, 2024, 2025), may make the person think or feel that it is justified to believe that p, and may make the person think or feel that she simply knows that p.

As a result, the person may find herself in an epistemically dilemmic situation: on the one hand, she faces and, to varying extents, recognises the independent evidence against her belief, but on the other hand, she experiences a strong seeming that compels the belief. No epistemic norm is easily available for one to resolve this tension (for an inverse case where the seeming is true and the independent evidence is false, see Williamson, 2025). What the person ultimately believes depends on a complex interaction between her seeming and her consideration of the independent evidence. The interaction may differ from case to case. Whenever a false seeming prevails, the person will end up with an irrational belief in the face of counterevidence.


The new approach


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...