This post is by Chenwei Nie (University of Warwick). In this post, Chenwei discusses a proposal detailed in his new chapter, "Why rational people obstinately hold onto irrational beliefs: A new approach", to appear in a book entitled Epistemic Dilemmas and Epistemic Normativity (Routledge).
![]() |
Chenwei Nie |
In the middle of this brutal summer, with scorching heatwaves across Europe, Asia, and North America, it is poignant that so many believe that climate change is not real. Nearly 15% of Americans believe it is not real (Gounaridis & Newell, 2024), and among the members of the 118th US Congress, almost a quarter share this belief, who are all Republicans (So, 2024). Even more alarming, climate change denial is just one example in a much broader, unsettling set of irrational beliefs, including but not limited to cases of superstitious, religious, political, and conspiratorial beliefs. The burning question is: Why do people obstinately hold onto irrational beliefs in the face of counterevidence?
When a belief fails to be sensitive to evidence as it should and is epistemically irrational (Bortolotti, 2010), it is likely influenced by non-evidential factors that do not bear on the truth of the belief. In the case of climate denial, the non-evidential factors may include the denier’s anxiety over the catastrophic implications of climate change, her fondness for Trump whom she may take to be a climate denier as well, and her practical consideration that the belief solidifies her identity as a proud Republican. What is less clear is how exactly non-evidential factors contribute to the development of irrational beliefs.
Existing approaches often assume that non-evidential factors either distort the way the person collects and evaluates independent evidence or are taken by the person as evidence for her belief (Schleifer McCormick, 2020; Glüer & Wikforss, 2022; Simion, 2024; Flores, forthcoming).
![]() |
Existing approaches |
As a result, the person may find herself in an epistemically dilemmic situation: on the one hand, she faces and, to varying extents, recognises the independent evidence against her belief, but on the other hand, she experiences a strong seeming that compels the belief. No epistemic norm is easily available for one to resolve this tension (for an inverse case where the seeming is true and the independent evidence is false, see Williamson, 2025). What the person ultimately believes depends on a complex interaction between her seeming and her consideration of the independent evidence. The interaction may differ from case to case. Whenever a false seeming prevails, the person will end up with an irrational belief in the face of counterevidence.
![]() |
The new approach |