Skip to main content

Conceptual Competences in Philosophy of Psychiatry

This week we are happy to have Christophe Gauld and colleagues presenting a recent paper investigating philosophical conceptual competence among French psychiatrists. 


Christophe Gauld

A recent international study published in L’Encéphale aim to offer an overview of how psychiatry residents and psychiatrists in France relate to conceptual and philosophical aspects of their discipline. Based on responses from 353 participants, the survey highlights a strong endorsement (over 90%) for integrating philosophy into psychiatry curricula, with a more cautious self-assessment of conceptual confidence.
 
This result highlights a situation where interest and perceived importance coexist with limited perceived preparedness. While 80% support the development of specific conceptual skills, many respondents report uncertainty or limited familiarity with the relevant philosophical frameworks. Such findings suggest that the place of conceptual reflection in psychiatric training remains potentially underdeveloped and would benefit from clearer educational pathways.
 
Philosophy of psychiatry is concerned with how we understand mental health and illness, not just through clinical categories or biological mechanisms, but also through the frameworks we use to define, explain and engage with these conditions. Issues such as the status of psychiatric diagnoses, the role of values in clinical reasoning, or the diversity of explanatory models are regularly encountered in practice, even if not always explicitly addressed.
 
In this study, participants were invited to evaluate their engagement with three types of conceptual competences: integration (how often they consider conceptual issues in their training and clinical reasoning), execution (their confidence in applying such reasoning), and knowledge (their agreement with key philosophical insights). While knowledge scored relatively high, confidence in applying these competences remained limited. One notable result, for instance, is that only 4.2% of participants strongly agreed that they feel confident identifying the assumptions that shape their clinical approach.


 

The study also explored how clinicians conceptualize psychiatric conditions. Among six descriptors presented, “disorder” and “dysfunction” were the most commonly endorsed. This pattern suggests that psychiatric conditions are primarily seen in terms of functional deviation – rather than biological disease or social meaning. Such tendencies echo debates in philosophy of psychiatry (e.g., related to the prominence of frameworks such as Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis, even when not explicitly named).

Finally, the study confirms that familiarity with philosophical issues is associated with higher self-reported competence across all dimensions. Age and level of training, by contrast, were not predictive. This reinforces the idea that exposure to these debates (whether through teaching, discussion, or interdisciplinary work) can make a tangible difference.
 
In response to this need, several programs have emerged internationally to support conceptual reflection in psychiatry, including electives, reading groups, and dedicated courses. In France, the inter-university diploma "Philosophies de la psychiatrie" has developed an interesting curriculum that combines theoretical knowledge with reflective and experiential learning.

Rather than treating philosophy as an abstract concern, this work shows its relevance for clinical care and education. By clarifying the tools and perspectives available, and sustaining reflective practice, philosophy can contribute meaningfully to how psychiatry understands itself, and how it evolves.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...