Skip to main content

Egocentric Representation: a Positive Dimension to Abnormal Self-Experience in Schizophrenia?

 
Gregory Yates
In schizophrenia, the basic experience of existing as a “self” – as a subject whose thoughts, beliefs and actions coincide with what is regarded to be “self” – is disturbed. This has been hypothesised as the distinct phenotypic core of schizophrenia (Sass and Parnas, 2003; Parnas et al., 2005) and the central psychopathological trait marker of psychotic vulnerability (Nelson et al., 2008; Parnas et al., 2005) 'The clinical symptoms come and go,' describes one schizophrenia patient, 'but this nothingness of self is permanently there.' (Kean, 2009)

Anomalous self-experiences (ASEs) provide much of the material for delusional beliefs formed in acute schizophrenia (Stanghellini, 2012). In line with my last post on this blog, I would like to consider whether ASEs might also provide a ‘secondary gain’ or epistemic benefit (Graham, 2013). I will examine one delusion frequently reported by schizophrenia patients, and highly suggestive of an ASE: the delusion of reference.
 
Delusions of reference are ‘beliefs that a wide variety of neutral events have special significance and refer to the individual personally’ (see Startup and Startup, 2005) A typical example is recounted by Kendler (1999), whose patient R recalls entering a stadium full of people and becoming convinced that he was being watched and applauded by all of them. What underlies a delusion such as this is egocentricity – an ASE entailing a felt “link” between the self and the world inhabited by it (Parnas et al., 2005

As an abnormality of subjective orientation (Mishara, 2005; Gallagher,1985), egocentric representation (ER) of the self/world relation can be contrasted to allocentric representation (AR), which utilises visual scene context, rather than the self, as the frame of reference for conceptualising the self/world relation (Mishara, 2005
 
Delusions of reference demonstrate that ER is capable of “fooling” schizophrenia patients into forming maladaptive beliefs. But what these notorious delusions perhaps obscure, as I will now show, is that ER can also provide unique protections against being “fooled”.
Granted, AR is an extremely practical mode of self-world experience. Without AR, schizophrenia patients experience significant difficulties in using complex visual context to guide action, which results in impaired performance on a variety of tasks, such as those involving perceptual closure of incomplete objects (Doniger et al., 2001) and determination of relative relationships between visual objects (Mishara, 2005)
But AR is not infallible. In tasks where visual context is misleading, AR is disadvantageous. Take the classic Müller-Lyer illusion, pictured below:

 

The horizontal bar appears longer when the arrowheads are pointing inwards, but in reality both bars are of identical length:


Overcoming the Müller-Lyer illusion requires “filtering out” misleading context provided by the arrowheads – a cognitive strategy that does not come naturally to many. Yet, to schizophrenia patients, whose egocentric self-experience precludes use of this sort of context in the first place, this is no difficulty: they excel at Müller-Lyer tasks relative to “normals” (Parnas, 1999) Indeed, they excel to a degree similar to patients with stroke lesions damaging the ventral pathway, which has led some clinicians to suggest increased reliance on dorsal-stream processing as a cause of ASEs in schizophrenia (Mishara, 2005).
The epistemic superiority of ER to AR on tasks such as the Müller-Lyer challenge can be taken as further evidence that (1) cognitive abnormalities in schizophrenia are context-dependent and, (2) there exists the possibility of a significant positive dimension to psychosis.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph