Ema Sullivan-Bissett |
In my last blog post I wrote
about mine and Paul Noordhof’s work on relationist accounts of experience and
delusional belief formation. The conclusion from that post was that the
relationist who denies phenomenal character to hallucinatory experience could
not accept any empiricist account (an account which gives anomalous experience
a role in the explanation of delusion formation) of what we called ‘positive
delusions’ (delusions involving hallucinatory experience). This meant that the
relationist must adopt a rationalist account of delusion formation, an account
which refuses ‘to ground the delusion in an abnormal experience’ (Bayne and Pacherie 2004: 81).
We think this means that relationism incurs a considerable
cost—those delusions arising from positive experiences require a completely
different theory: not a one-stage empiricist theory, nor even a two-stage
theory, but rather a rationalist theory. Relationism forces one into
recognising a discontinuity in the nature of delusion that there seems no reason
to recognise from the study of delusion alone.
We think that this is not the
end of the ramifications for our target relationist: in having to adopt a
rationalist account of delusion formation, the relationist cannot adopt either a
teleological account or a normative account of belief.
Paul Noordhof |
The teleological account of
belief holds that belief is a constitutively aim-governed activity such that ‘believing that p
essentially involves having as an aim to believe p truly’ (Steglich-Petersen 2009: 395). This aim is realised in one of two ways. In the deliberative case,
where the subject deliberates over what to believe, the aim of belief is
realised in the subject’s aim qua a
believer. In the non-deliberative case, where the subject comes to have beliefs
without deliberation (for example, beliefs arising out of perception), the aim
of belief is realised by ‘some sub-intentional surrogate of such intentions in
the form of truth-regulated […] mechanisms’ (Steglich-Petersen 2006: 510).
What
teleological theorists might be inclined to say about delusion is the
following: the delusional subject aims to believe that p only if p is true, and in doing so she adopts what strikes her as a plausible
hypothesis given her anomalous experience. She is sensitive to
evidential considerations in the normal way. If the teleologist says this,
delusional beliefs are going to present an unproblematic case. The subject
still aims at truth—she just misses—owing to her being led astray by her
anomalous experience.
However, this line is ruled out
by a rationalist account of delusional belief formation and hence is not
available to our target relationist. As we saw, rationalist accounts claim that
delusions are not grounded in any abnormal experience of the subject, belief
formation is the result of injury alone, there is no consideration of evidence
and no rationalisation of one’s experiences. This account of delusion is
incompatible with the teleological line sketched above, because on the rationalist
story a delusional belief is not formed as a result of any intention of the
agent.
Maybe the relationist has
recourse to the claim that delusions are non-deliberative beliefs, so in cases
of delusion the agent need not have the aim of regarding p as true only
if it really is. However the relationist must then say why delusions still come
out as beliefs on the teleological account. They could say that delusions
are regulated for truth (by some sub-intentional mechanism), and it is because
of this truth regulation—which they share with deliberative beliefs—that they
are classified as beliefs on this account (Steglich-Petersen 2006: 511).
However, this does not help the
relationist because on the rationalist account, not even this sort of regulation
is going on: delusions do not look to have been regulated by truth at all.
On the rationalist account the subject’s anomalous experiences play no role
in the belief formation, so it is not open to the relationist attracted to the
teleological account to claim that one’s delusional belief has been
sub-intentionally regulated for truth on the basis of the subject’s
experiences. If the rationalist account of delusion is right then, the
teleological account of belief is false.
Our target relationist then has
to rule out empiricist accounts of delusional belief formation. His remaining
option is to adopt a rationalist account. However, if one is a rationalist
about delusional belief formation, one’s options for accounting for the
connection between belief and truth become limited, one cannot accept the teleological account of belief. In the next post I’ll write about why we also think our
target relationist has to also rule out the normative account of belief.