Skip to main content

What's Positive about Positive Illusions?

Positive illusions provide a challenge to the once-accepted view that accurate beliefs about oneself and the world are conducive to wellbeing and mental health. Illusions are "beliefs that depart from reality" and they are positive when they involve unrealistic optimism about one's capacities, prospects, or control over the external environment. 

We can find three broad types of positive illusions, following Taylor and Brown (1994): (1) excessively positive self-appraisals; (2) the belief that one has greater control over events than it is actually the case; (3) more rosy views of the future than statistics can warrant. It is important that positive illusions are regarded as mild distortions of reality and do not involve "denying the obvious": most researchers interested in positive illusions are keen to distinguish positive illusions from cases of self-deception or from defence mechanisms. Taylor and Brown have shown not only that positive illusions are widespread in non-clinical populations, but that there are strong links between certain forms of positive illusion and the promotion of mental health (in terms of creativity and productivity), and physical health (in terms of prolonged longevity). 

A classic example of positive illusions is the better-than-most effect. People tend to find themselves warmer, kinder, more sincere, etc., than the average person and these "self-aggrandising" views are correlated with higher achievement. Similar results have been found with young children overestimating their capacities. They develop better language, problem-solving, or motor skills. 

People affected by serious illness who believe that they are coping better than other patients are found to experience reduced stress. Another classic example concerns illusions of control. In a lottery situation, people who have been assigned random tickets prefer to swap their tickets with tickets they choose themselves, even if this does not impact on their chances to win (Langer 1975). People's belief that they can change alter external circumstances for the better, when the circumstances are such that they can be to an extent changed, contributes to better adjustment in context of trauma or chronic illness. 

Finally, unrealistic optimism is  the phenomenon by which "people anticipate that their future will be brighter than can reasonably be justified on statistical grounds" (Taylor and Brown 1994). People who are optimistic in this way are more creative, and cope better with stressful situations. Taylor et al. (1992) studied men who had tested seropositive for HIV and found that they were more optimistic about not acquiring AIDS than men who knew they were seronegative. This (illusory) optimism was correlated to health-promoting behaviour and use of positive coping techniques.

Now, this is all good, but can positive illusions be also epistemically beneficial? In the endless source of wisdom that is McKay and Dennett (2009), we find some suggestions about epistemic features of positive illusions. First, the authors argue that positive illusions are both psychologically and biologically adaptive, because they do not just make people feel better about themselves, but can improve physical health too, and have evolutionarily relevant benefits. One example is parenting. The better-than-average effect applies not just to oneself but also to one's romantic partner, and seeing one's partner as better than the average partner in intelligence, attractiveness, etc. (Gagné and Lydon 2004) is good for the relationship and (maybe less romantically) matters to the efficient "completion of species-specific parental duties". If the relationship lasts, the offspring receives better care and more protection, so she is more likely to survive and flourish. Similarly, people have inflated views of their own children (Wenger and Fowers 2008), which makes parents more attached to their children, and more willing to dedicate time and resources to them.

More interesting from our point of view, if it is true that unrealistically positive views of, and a sense of control over, one's medical history increase health and longevity (Taylor et al. 2003), then, as McKay and Dennett notice, the optimism of positive illusions is "not so unrealistic after all". The belief that one will be healthy and live longer is no longer unjustified, because it acts as a self-fulfilling prophecy and it becomes true. McKay and Dennett conclude that: "such doxastic departures from reality are not culpable but entirely forgivable". In the light of their epistemic features, maybe we could even say that some positive illusions do not really count as departures from reality at all.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph