Skip to main content

Consciousness and Moral Responsibility

Consciousness and Moral Responsibility
By Neil Levy
This book aims to contribute to debates within moral philosophy and in philosophy of mind.

There has been a lot of debate in recent years focusing on the relationship between consciousness and moral responsibility. Some of this debate has been spurred by work in neuroscience and in social psychology, which allegedly shows that we lack ‘conscious will’: we are not conscious of the volitions that actually cause our actions. This work has been taken by some neuroscientists to threaten moral responsibility: “We do not hold people responsible for actions performed unconsciously, without the possibility of conscious control”, Libet claims. On the other hand, and quite independently of concerns over these alleged threats, a number of philosophers have recently argued that consciousness is not needed for moral responsibility at all: that we can be morally responsible for actions while unconscious of the reasons for which we act.

While these two parallel debates have produce a great deal of valuable work, they have not intersected. Moreover, neither has made any reference to the rich body of work on the neuroscience of consciousness. In fact we know a great deal about consciousness, from careful experimental work which compares the behavior and the neural correlates of subjects who can report a stimulus versus those who cannot. This work demonstrates that consciousness is not necessary for responding to a stimulus, but that there are systematic differences in the behavior of people who are conscious of the representations they are responding to, versus those who are not. On this basis, we are able to develop an account of the basis and functional role of consciousness.

The account of consciousness I defend in the book is a version of the global workspace account, first developed by Bernard Baars. According to this account (as I develop it), when information is conscious it is available to all or most of the consuming systems that compose the mind, whereas when information is processed in the absence of consciousness its contents are available only to a relatively narrow range of these systems. But the things that make us who we are as individuals – our beliefs, principles, and so on – are distributed across the brain. This entails, I claim, that when responses are driven by a relatively narrow range of consuming systems, they are not fully expressive of the person, nor fully controlled by the person. Expression of the person and control are, I argue, the two most plausible necessary conditions for moral responsibility. In many circumstances, this loss of the expression relation and of robust control is sufficient to eliminate moral responsibility; responsibility is eliminated because consciousness is eliminated. Therefore, consciousness is, after all, a necessary condition of moral responsibility.

I argue that attention to actual cases of people performing morally significant actions while in states that involve absence of or greatly reduced consciousness supports this claim. Behaviours in these states is inflexible and stereotyped: just what one would expect given that the information is not available to a broad range of consuming systems. Extending the theory, I argue that people in ordinary states of consciousness may have their moral responsibility greatly reduced or eliminated by absence of consciousness of some content to which they nevertheless respond. Of course, the theory is heavily empirical, and perhaps its claims may not stand up to future scrutiny. However our philosophy ought to be responsive to good science; the risks of refutation may be greater, but we gain in confidence that our theories are grounded in the nature of the world.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...