Skip to main content

Diagnosing the DSM

Rachel Cooper
I’m a philosopher working mainly on conceptual problems surrounding the DSM (the main classification of mental disorders used by psychiatrists). This post looks at how a certain type of epistemic imperfection – ambiguity – can be the strategically useful, by considering the definition of mental disorder in the most recent edition of the DSM (DSM-5, published 2013).  

During its development, two distinct definitions of “mental disorder” were drafted for the DSM-5. The first was an iteration of the previous DSM definition and took mental disorder to be a value-laden concept, i.e. it claimed that disorders are necessarily harmful. The second definition characterized mental disorder as mental dysfunction, and aimed to offer a value-free account. The working groups said that a decision between these two definitions would be made at a later date. Note that philosophers of medicine generally hold that value-laden and value-free accounts of disorder are competing accounts. To be consistent one has to opt for one or the other.

However, when the DSM-5 was finally published, the definition of ‘disorder’ sought a compromise between the two draft definitions. According to the DSM-5,

"A mental disorder is a syndrome characterized by clinically significant disturbance in an individual’s cognition, emotion regulation, or behaviour that reflects a dysfunction in the psychological, biological, or developmental processes underlying mental functioning. Mental disorders are usually associated with significant distress or disability in social, occupational, or other important activities…" (emphasis added, DSM-5, p. 20)

This definition bears no resemblance to the sorts of definition via necessary and sufficient conditions that philosophers tend to propose; in any particular case it is unclear whether harm is needed prior to diagnosis or not. Philosophers tend to think that clarity is a good thing, and from such a stance the DSM-5 definition of mental disorder looks to be a very bad definition.

However, a different tradition has it that in certain contexts ambiguity may be useful, and rather than being refined away, may be retained, or even created. In The Concept of Law (1961), H.L.A. Hart discusses the “open texture” of language, and how it enables judges to employ sensible discretion in the application of rules. The rule may say “No vehicles in the park” but the ambiguity of “vehicle” means that the judge is left free to make sensible and context-specific decisions about bikes, wheelchairs, skateboards and so on. Specifying in advance exactly what would count as a “vehicle” would not be helpful.

The definition of “mental disorder” included in the DSM-5 can perhaps best be understood as answering such goals. In failing to provide necessary and sufficient criteria for a condition to count as a disorder it places no constraints on what might be added to the classification in the future. And, from a certain point of view this might be considered a useful feature. Those who speak ambiguously now, leave themselves free to claim what they wish later.

This article has been posted on behalf of Rachel Cooper, who is a senior lecturer in philosophy at Lancaster University.

Her new book Diagnosing the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders will be published by Karnac later this year.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph