Skip to main content

Epistemic Innocence (part 4)

This is the fourth in a series of posts Lisa and I are writing on Epistemic Innocence. So far Lisa has introduced the two conditions we think characterize epistemic innocence, I have written about the Availability Condition, and Lisa has written about the Epistemic Benefit condition. In this post I want to outline some reasons for thinking that delusional beliefs, at least sometimes, meet these two conditions. In her next post, Lisa will apply the notion of epistemic innocence to memory.


The No Relevant Alternatives Condition

The claim that delusions meet the No Relevant Alternatives Condition is supported by Daniel Freeman and colleagues' study on alternative explanations. Subjects with delusions were asked about the evidence for their delusional beliefs and the ‘availability of alternative explanations’ (Freeman et al. 2004: 677). Freeman and colleagues conclude from the study that:


‘we have found evidence that (at least at the height of the episode) individuals do not have accessible alternative explanations for their experiences. This seems to be caused by (a) a lack of awareness and knowledge about internal anomalous experiences, (b) reasoning biases, and (c) the difficulty of conceiving alternatives that are as compelling as the delusions in explaining personal experiences’
(Freeman et al. 2004: 679, my emphasis).

Coltheart and colleagues' (2009) work on abductive inference and delusional belief also supports the claim that delusions meet the No Relevant Alternatives Condition. Coltheart and colleagues argue that subjects with delusions form beliefs in line with a Bayesian model of abductive inference, according to which ‘one hypothesis 
H1 explains observations O better than another hypothesis H2 just in case P(O│H1) > P(O│H2)’ (Coltheart et al. 2009: 276).

Coltheart and colleagues think that the delusional hypothesis is more probable than the non-delusional hypothesis, given the observed phenomenon. Considering a case of the Capgras delusion, the two hypotheses in play are the stranger hypothesis (the woman who looks like my wife is not my wife) and the wife hypothesis (the woman who looks like my wife is my wife):


‘the observed data are clearly much more likely under the stranger hypothesis than under the wife hypothesis. It would be highly improbable for the subject to have the low autonomic response if the person really was his wife, but very probable indeed if the person were a stranger’
(Coltheart et al. 2009: 277).

Coltheart and colleagues' work here suggests that non-delusional alternative hypotheses are unavailable to subjects insofar as they are explanatorily unavailable. The delusional hypothesis just does a much better job of explaining the observed data, if what we mean by doing a better job is cashed out in terms of Bayesian probabilities.

The Epistemic Benefit Condition

What kinds of epistemic benefits might delusions enjoy? One benefit might be the filling of an explanatory gap. The subject may have an anomalous experience which they cannot explain, this may create in the subject ‘puzzlement, anxiety, and a search for an explanation’ (Maher 2006: 181). Perhaps the delusional hypothesis which makes some sense of the experience is better than no hypothesis at all (given the No Relevant Alternatives condition, there is no alternative). Maher suggests that delusional hypotheses are best thought of as like scientific theories—both ‘serve the purpose of providing order and meaning for empirical data obtained by observation’ (Maher 1988: 20). If this is right, the delusion is epistemically beneficial in providing an explanation of an as yet unexplained phenomenon.

Delusions might also be epistemically beneficial insofar as they make other perceptual beliefs coherent. A subject’s belief that she sees a second head on her shoulder, or that the person in the mirror does not look like her, might be made sense of by a delusional belief.

Delusions may also have indirect epistemic benefits. Maher suggests that for subjects with delusions, coherent explanations of their experiences are often accompanied by a ‘strong feeling of personal relief’, as well as the excitement a scientist might get from intellectual insight (Maher 1974: 104). The explanation for the anomalous experience that the delusional subject comes to may provide ‘enough relief from anxiety that it becomes difficult for the individual to abandon it and return to the initial state of confusion and distress’ (
Maher 2006: 182). This relief from anxiety may have indirect epistemic benefits if the anxiety felt before coming to the delusional explanation for the anomalous experience was such as to adversely affect wellbeing and compromise the gaining of knowledge.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph