Skip to main content

Workshop on Costs and Benefits of Imperfect Cognitions


On 8th-9th May Lisa Bortolotti and Ema Sullivan-Bissett hosted a workshop as part of the AHRC-funded project on the Epistemic Innocence of Imperfect Cognitions at the University of Birmingham. Papers were given by Ryan McKay (Royal Holloway), Maarten Boudry (Ghent), Lisa Bortolotti (Birmingham), Katerina Fotopoulou (UCL), Martin Conway (City University London), Ema Sullivan-Bissett (Birmingham), Petter Johansson (Lund), Lars Hall (Lund), Jules Holroyd (Nottingham), and Miranda Fricker (Sheffield).
McKay on false beliefs

McKay and Boudry opened the workshop with their discussion 'In Defence of False Beliefs?'; they approached the discussion as a mock trial with McKay arguing for the 'defence' and Boudry arguing for the 'prosecution'. McKay argued that there may be social, psychological, biological, and epistemic benefits to having false beliefs and also that they should be considered rational as they seem to be properly responsive to evidence. Boudry countered that although we sometimes tolerate false beliefs these should not be considered rational; because we cannot tell which false beliefs are safe to indulge in and which are harmful, and we still need some people to keep track of the truth of the matter epistemically speaking.


Bortolotti on delusions
Next, Bortolotti presented a paper entitled 'Epistemic Costs and Benefits of Delusional Beliefs', in which she introduced the notion of 'epistemic innocence' and discussed whether clinical delusions, such as schizophrenia, have the potential for epistemic innocence. She argued that at least some delusions can have temporary epistemic benefits as well as psychological benefits. But she was keen to note that this does not mean that epistemically innocent beliefs are free from epistemic faults, are epistemically neutral, or are epistemically good or justified as a result of her argument.

After lunch Fotopoulou gave a paper entitled 'Inferring the Self: Neurological Exaggerations of Normally Imperfect Inferences about the Body', where she discussed how we become aware of ourselves in the world with reference to cases of neurological disorders and clinical cases. She went on to describe how neurological disorders of the bodily self represent exaggerated instances of normally imperfect inferences about one's bodily state and the self.

Conway on memory
Then Conway gave a paper entitled 'Memory, Reality, and Consciousness in the Remembering-Imagining System', in which he explored recent themes relating to autobiographical memory. He was particularly interested in whether such memory represented reality, and he went on to argue that autobiographical memory represents experienced reality; before turning to discuss the connections between what is remembered and what is imagined.

Finally, Sullivan-Bissett closed the first day with her paper on 'The Epistemic Status of Confabulatory Explanations'. Here she argued that there is a sense in which confabulatory explanations can have epistemic benefits by discussing cases in the clinical population, and various implications for clinical intervention; before explaining that confabulatory explanations as such can be considered epistemically innocent.

The second day began with a paper by Johansson and Hall entitled 'Choice Blindness and the Flexibility of Attitude Formation: Why not Knowing why might be a Good Thing'. Here they discussed recent studies involving 'choice blindness' (which was originally inspired by techniques in close-up-card-magic) and moral and political attitudes. They discussed the flexibility of the research participants attitudes and argued that this can be considered a good thing because people seem to be more open to changing their moral and political opinions than had been previously assumed.

Next Holroyd presented a paper entitled 'Implicit Bias, Awareness Conditions, and Epistemic Innocence' in which she explored whether individuals are morally responsible for expressing implicit bias in their actions and she went on to argue that individuals should have awareness of the morally undesirable property of their actions as implicitly biased. Though she noted that whether people are responsible for implicitly biased actions depends on whether failures to know this are blameworthy; and this in turn depends on the relationship between implicit biases and other imperfect cognitions, which she claimed may have a role in sustaining ignorance of blame about our biased
Holroyd on implicit bias
behaviour.

Finally, Fricker closed the workshop with her paper entitled 'Fault and No-fault Epistemic Responsibility for Implicit Prejudice'. Here she discussed the question of whether there are circumstances where we may be guilty of implicit prejudice and yet not be epistemically blameworthy. She used the example of bad epistemic luck, where there is a space for no-fault epistemic responsibility, which she argued should be considered the epistemic analogue of 'agent regret' as found in normative debates.

Overall the conference had a relaxed and engaging atmosphere, with lots of time for productive discussion over the two days. More information about the project, including a full list of outputs and calendar of research activities can be found here and the project Facebook page and Twitter feed can be used to stay in touch with the Imperfect Cognitions network activities.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph