Skip to main content

Beauty and Imperfect Cognitions

We are posting this on behalf of Professor Heather Widdows (University of Birmingham) who recently gave a talk on beauty as a topic in philosophy and ethics at the Hay Festival.


Heather Widdows
I'm John Ferguson Professor of Global Ethics in the department of Philosophy at the University of Birmingham. My current work is on ideals of perfection and beauty and I'm in the progress of writing Perfect Me! (under contract with Princeton University Press). In this book I’m exploring contemporary ideals of beauty and all the gory details which attach to messy, smelly, hairy, saggy and ever-changing human bodies from the perspective of moral philosophy.

In Perfect Me! I consider three key ways in which the (moral) ideal of beauty functions. First, as an individual’s aspiration to perfect themselves (‘I want to be perfect’) – a value judgement – that this type of beauty is worth having – a moral claim; second, as assertion of what being perfect is (‘this is what I would be if I were perfect’) – a judgement about what perfect in this context is; and third, as a command which a woman (or a man) feels she or he should obey (‘you should be perfect’) – so a moral imperative – directed towards this perfect ideal, which implies that beauty is some ‘good’ to be striven for.

This work is only tangentially relevant to imperfect cognitions and the work of the Epistemic Innocence project, however there are potentially some areas of overlap. One area is about decision-making and the assumptions about what fully informed means when it comes to engaging in beauty practices and procedures. My work is in its early stages but one of the arguments I make is about the power of the ‘imagined self’ and its strength in the dominant beauty ideal and the language which surrounds beauty. The language of the beauty discourse is morally coloured – literally saturated with value. It constantly suggests the importance of striving for your better/more perfect self; phrases such as ‘your best self’ or ‘the best you can be’ or ‘it’s still you, but the best version of you’. It assumes that this matters – ‘you’re worth it’, ‘you owe it to yourself’; and conversely that failure to strive for that more perfect you, that better self, makes you culpable and blameworthy – you ‘let yourself go’ and presumably ‘you’re not worth it’.

In this ideal beauty, happiness and success begin to merge, and ‘rewards’ are associated with attaining the ideal (rewards such as better jobs, better relationships and, in general, more happiness). One of the claims I make (and I’m missing out lots of the steps here) is about the power of the ‘imagined self’. That the self is becoming not only identified with the body (an old claim), but that the self is becoming further dislocated and identified with the imagined body – the body that I will have – once I have lost the weight I need to; firmed my thighs in the way I should; sorted out my hair and erased my wrinkles. The power of this ideal is such that it brings into question the validity of consent in the context of beauty. This is for a large number of reasons but to name just two which might have some relevance to imperfect cognitions.

(1) The power of the imagined self over decision-making makes claims of being fully informed questionable. For example, being fully informed requires knowing and being able to assess the risks and benefits. However, arguably those who engage in at least some kinds of beauty practices do so not only despite the risks, but often ignoring or playing down the risks. This claim is not that information is not given – it is – but rather about how it is understood. I suggest that the power of the imagined self – the end point of the ideal – is so powerful it distorts the risks and therefore makes them harder to assess.

(2) The whole language surrounding beauty is individual (about the best you) and yet these beauty values are largely shared (in the book there are arguments about the homogenising nature of the current beauty ideal). Given this, to claim that consent is just a matter of separate individual choices is deeply problematic. You can’t choose your own beauty ideal; you can only choose to conform to it, to embody it or to reject it.

My research will be funded by a Major Leverhulme Fellowship and a larger discussion of the work was given at the Hay Festival this year.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...