Skip to main content

Are Delusions Acceptances?

Keith Frankish
If psychotic patients did not tell us, would we guess what their delusions were? We might see that a patient was depressed, withdrawn, self-neglecting, and so on, but would it occur to us that they thought they were dead, as Cotard patients do? It is doubtful. Deluded patients are firmly attached to their delusions, but the attachment manifests itself most clearly at the verbal level, in what they say and how they argue, and may not show up clearly in their nonverbal behaviour. Most Cotard patients do not (as one early case did) arrange their own funeral.

Why is this? The answer, I think, is that delusion is an attitude closely bound up with language -- an attitude sometimes called ‘acceptance’. To accept a proposition, in this sense, is to commit oneself to arguing for it, defending it, using in reasoning, and acting upon it. This is the attitude a scientist takes to a hypothesis, a lawyer to the claim that their client is innocent, a politician to a policy. It is a sort of intellectual commitment, which is active, reflective, and conscious. (For more on acceptance and a detailed presentation of the case for thinking that delusions are acceptances, see this paper.)

If delusions are acceptances, then several things follow. I shall mention three. First, delusions are active. Accepting a proposition involves making and executing a commitment to a certain pattern of argumentation and reasoning. Thus, deluded patients are actively engaging with their situation rather than just passively responding to it.

Second, delusion is motivated. We accept propositions because doing so answers some need or goal (not necessarily a conscious one). This might be simply the goal of accepting truths, but it could be pragmatic, as in the case of the lawyer. Thus, a new question arises about delusions: What need or goal does the formation of a delusion address? It could be epistemic; maybe the patient is just trying to make sense of their distorted experiences. But a delusion might serve other psychological needs, especially emotional ones. For example, it might be a comfort to have a simple framework for representing what is happening to one, however bizarre.

Third, delusions have limited behavioural influence. Acceptance does influence nonverbal behaviour -- the commitment extends to acting upon the accepted proposition -- but this influence is often limited. An acceptance may be deliberately restricted in scope (the lawyer accepts her client’s innocence for professional purposes only), and even if it isn’t, it won’t automatically guide routine behaviour. Acting upon an acceptance requires paying attention to what one is doing and deliberately regulating one’s behaviour to bring it in line with the proposition accepted. Moreover, even if one realizes that an acceptance dictates a certain action, one’s desire to adhere to it might be overridden by other desires. (Think of the effort involved in adhering to a moral principle one has accepted.) Thus, delusions will only influence behaviour that is under reflective control and may influence that only in a patchy way. This does not mean that a patient’s unreflective behaviour will be normal, of course. But it will manifest their distress in a raw uninterpreted form, rather than one constrained to reflect the pattern imposed by their delusion.

The idea that delusions are acceptances has been discussed before on this blog, but it has not received a lot of attention, perhaps because the literature on acceptance is not itself widely known. I hope this will change and that the hypothesis will be explored and evaluated in clinical contexts.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...