Skip to main content

Questions and Reasoning in Schizophrenia and Delusion


Matthew Parrott
Schizophrenia and delusion are typically described as involving some kind of impairment in a subject's ability to reason (e.g., Coltheart et. al., 2011; Coltheart, 2007; Davies and Egan 2013; Garety and Freeman, 1999). Yet, although there is evidence indicating that subjects diagnosed with these psychiatric conditions reason in anomalous ways, in many cases the pattern of reasoning they exhibit looks to be more optimal than the one exhibited by non-psychiatric controls. Most famously, we have known for a number of years that both schizophrenic and delusional subjects 'jump to conclusions' on probabilistic reasoning tasks (Fine, et. al., 2007) but their performance on these tasks is very close to a Bayesian model of ideal rationality. Secondly, there is some recent evidence that suggests schizophrenic subjects may be better at reasoning with conditionals. According to one study, they seem to be less susceptible to believability biases (Owen, et. al., 2007) and according to another they seem to be better at falsifying conditionals with negated antecedents (Mellet, et. al., 2006).
 
To improve our understanding of these intriguing phenomena, we need to understand precisely how the reasoning capacities of psychiatric subjects differ from those of other individuals. Yet existing theoretical models have failed to give us a clear picture of this. Investigations of reasoning in delusional and schizophrenic subjects have largely been conducted from within a Bayesian framework (Davies and Egan 2013Fine, et. al., 2007). Yet, despite the widespread popularity of this approach in the cognitive sciences, I think it faces certain difficulties, which, for reasons of space, I cannot go into here - although I'm happy to discuss in comments (cf. Parrott, forthcoming).

As an alternative to the Bayesian approach, Philipp Koralus and I are currently drawing on the Erotetic Theory of reasoning (Koralus and Macarenhas, 2013) in or to develop an account of the various patterns of reasoning demonstrated by psychiatric subjects. One of the central insights of the Erotetic framework is to view reasoning as a cognitive process that aims to answer questions, which the theory represents as sets of alternative possibilities.

The Erotetic Theory suggests an intriguing hypothesis: delusional and schizophrenic reasoning differs from that of non-psychiatric subjects in that it relies less on endogenously generated questions. This hypothesis actually predicts different patterns of success and failure: it predicts that subjects who generate fewer questions endogenously would require less empirical evidence before drawing conclusions and it also predicts that this very same tendency to generate fewer questions would actually lead psychiatric subjects to perform better on tasks involving reasoning with conditionals.

Moreover, the Erotetic framework also suggests two exciting clinical implications. First, rather than envisioning psychiatric conditions as based on some kind of deficit in thought or reasoning, the approach suggests that psychiatric patients may simply be less inquisitive in a certain technical sense. Second, the framework suggests that effective clinical interventions may consist in simply helping patients learn to raise the right sorts of questions.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...