Skip to main content

Oxford Loebel Lectures 2014 - Professor Kenneth S. Kendler

Kenneth Kendler
This is a report on the 2014 Oxford Loebel Lectures by Rebecca Roache, Lecturer in Philosophy at Royal Holloway, University of London.

The biopsychosocial model in psychiatry tells us that psychiatric disorders arise from a combination of biological, psychological, and social factors. But how do causes at these three ‘levels’ interact, and how do we put this insight to use in treating mental illness? Professor Kenneth Kendler addressed these questions in Oxford’s inaugural Loebel Lectures.

In his first lecture (which you can watch here or listen to here), Kendler shared fascinating empirical data to demonstrate the aetiological complexity of psychiatric disorders. He showed that whilst one’s genes can make it more likely that one will suffer certain disorders, the causal pathway does not run directly from genes to the development of a disorder. Rather, causal pathways often—to use Kendler’s expression—‘loop out’ into the environment. For example, having a genetic predisposition to depression makes you more likely to be depressed, but this is because you will be more sensitive than other people to stressful life events that can cause depression. Another example: alcohol dependency does not simply arise from one’s genes, but via one’s genetically-induced tendency to seek out social groups where drinking is encouraged.

In Kendler’s second lecture (view it here or listen here), he observed that before the middle of the 19th century, mental disorders were not thought to have single, clear aetiologies. This changed in the late 19th century, when scientific advances meant that various somatic diseases were explained in terms of elegant, simple causal mechanisms, paving the way for a reductionist quest to discover single causal aetiologies for psychiatric disorders. However, with the exception of the discovery that general paresis is caused by syphilis, attempts to discover such simple aetiologies have been unsuccessful.

What does this lack of success tell us? Kendler thinks that finding simple aetiologies for psychiatric disorders is an unrealistic goal, since there is generally no privileged level of explanation for these disorders in terms of which such aetiologies could be characterised. It is not the case, for example, that the best causal story for any given psychiatric disorder is one couched purely in terms of neuropathology, or molecular genetics, or environmental stressors, or some other narrowly-focused set of explanatory factors. On the contrary, invariably, we need to consider all these explanatory factors and more in order to explain psychiatric disorders: a phenomenon that Kendler terms ‘dappling’.

What should be the implications of all this for the way in which psychiatric disorders are conceptualised, diagnosed, and treated? Kendler advocates a technique that he calls epistemic iteration, in which researchers make a series of attempts to describe a given disorder, each of which improves on previous ones. To make progress in this area, Kendler argued that we must (1) adopt a pluralistic, broad-minded, and empirically rigorous approach to discovering the dappled causes of psychiatric disorders; (2) identify causal mechanisms, guidance about which can be found in the philosophy of biology literature; and (3) work on tracing aetiologic pathways back into neuropsychological terms and then ‘translating’ these third-person descriptions into the sort of first-person, mental language that captures the subjective experience of patients.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...