Skip to main content

The Epistemology of Religious Testimony

Boudewijn de Bruin
My name is Boudewijn de Bruin and I am Professor of Financial Ethics in the faculties of Economics and Business, and Philosophy, at the University of Groningen. 

In this post I will summarize a paper I wrote for a symposium organized at the occasion of the publication of Herman Philipse’s book God in the Age of Science in which he takes issue with Richard Swinburne’s attempts to provide evidence showing that the existence of God is highly probable.

Most evidence Swinburne marshals is publicly available. But some is only private: evidence gained through religious experience. Ideally Swinburne would not need private evidence, but, as he admits, all publicly available evidence is not by itself sufficiently strong for the unbeliever to be moved to adopt the belief that God exists.

The unbeliever needs religious experience, then, but it cannot be his or her own lest Swinburne only persuades those that have had an experience of God themselves. Swinburne therefore resorts to invoking testimonial evidence of ‘of-God experiences’, as he calls them.

Two things have to be shown then. The unbeliever has to have compelling evidence that, first of all, if someone has had of-God experiences, then they have had veridical experiences of God (Principle of Credulity); and secondly, that when someone reports having had of-God experiences, these reports are true (Principle of Testimony). Philipse attacks the Principle of Credulity. I argue that this attack may not be entirely convincing. Therefore I attack the Principle of Testimony.

God is an entity that is normally invisible and who can decide at will to give someone an of-God experience. Or so Swinburne holds. If this is the causal mechanism explaining the privacy of religious experience, the Principle of Testimony loses its appeal. Take bird-watching as an example. Suppose we both see a bird at the bottom of the garden and you rightly identify it as a bittern. This gives me some evidence about your bird-watching capacities, and therefore some reason confidently to apply the Principle of Testimony to your reports of of-bird experiences.

I can only be in the position to evaluate the applicability of the Principle of Testimony to a person S reporting of-O experiences if S and I have had joint experiences of O, though. And this is by definition impossible in the case of of-God experiences. God might give us both an of-God experience simultaneously, of course, but he would on Swinburne’s account be causing two separate religious experiences. Knowing that, S’s reporting an of-God experience coinciding with an of-God experience of mine would not give me any proof of S’s trustworthiness here. (And anyway, in such a case I would have my own private evidence and likely not feel the need to resort to S’s.)

One might object that if I dropped the implicit reductionist Humean view of testimony in favour of a Reidian view – Jonathan Adler’s Default Conception of Testimony, for instance – Swinburne’s argument might survive. It is widely accepted that a key challenge to Reidian approaches is to show that they do not make people too vulnerable to the whims of witnesses. Adler does indeed offer a number of clever solutions here. Yet while they may work for everyday testimonials, they do not work for reports of of-God experiences. 

These solutions require the opportunity to ascertain the trustworthiness of a potential source of information in the relevant domain. There is no such opportunity, however, as long as we do not have joint religious experiences. For the same reasons, the Humean and the Reidian unbeliever remain vulnerable, and should therefore suspend belief. Justified beliefs in God cannot come from others.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...