Skip to main content

A Virtue Theory of Memory (Error)

Today's post is by Kourken Michaelian (Centre for Philosophy of Memory, Université Grenoble Alpes).


Kourken Michaelian


With her 2016 article on misremembering, Sarah Robins drew the attention of philosophers of memory to the need to provide an account not only of successful remembering but also of unsuccessful remembering—an account of memory errors such as confabulation, to which William Hirstein had previously devoted a book but which had been neglected in subsequent discussions in the field.

The debate triggered by Robins’ article continues to unfold, with Robins herself defending an approach to memory errors inspired by the causal theory of memory in articles in 2019 and 2020, Sven Bernecker defending a similar causalist approach in an article in 2017, and myself defending an approach based on the simulation theory of memory in articles in 2016 and 2020. There are other approaches that merit discussion; André Sant’Anna, for example, argues in a forthcoming article that relationalist approaches to memory have difficulty accommodating unsuccessful remembering.

But the debate so far has unfolded primarily between causalists and simulationists, with the former holding that unsuccessful remembering is characterized by the lack of an appropriate causal connection between the apparent memory and the apparently remembered event and simulationists holding that it is characterized not by lack of appropriate causation but rather by the unreliability of the memory process.

 

Robins’ and Bernecker’s recent articles both develop versions of the causalist approach and attack the simulationist approach, and, in my article forthcoming in Synthese“Imagining the past reliably and unreliably: Towards a virtue theory of memory”—I respond to these attacks. But I also argue that, for reasons internal to simulationism, existing versions of the simulationist approach are inadequate. I argue, in particular, that they fail to fully acknowledge the involvement of a form of mnemic luck in many instances of unsuccessful remembering.

Mnemic luck is broadly analogous to the form of epistemic luck involved in Gettier cases, and the paper sketches a potential analogy between the development of the family of externalist epistemologies and the development of the family of (post)causal theories of memory of which simulationism is a member. Simplifying greatly, we might say that the limitations of the causal theory of knowledge led to the emergence of the process reliabilist theory of knowledge and that the limitations of process reliabilism led reliabilists to move to the virtue reliabilist theory of knowledge. Similarly, the limitations of the causal theory of memory led to the emergence of the simulation theory of memory (modelled on process reliabilism), and the limitations of simulationism suggest that simulationists move to a virtue reliability theory of memory.

The paper therefore proposes a new form of simulationism, a virtue theory of memory modelled not on process reliabilism but instead on virtue reliabilism and intended to handle mnemic luck in a manner roughly analogous to that in which virtue reliabilism handles epistemic luck. The paper argues that this new theory grounds a more adequate approach to unsuccessful remembering.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph