Skip to main content

Monothematic Delusions and the Limits of Rationality

Today's post is by Quinn Hiroshi Gibson and Adam Bradley, on how to understand monothematic delusions.

Quinn Hiroshi Gibson


Subjects with Capgras delusion form the delusion that a loved one has been replaced by an imposter:

The day after her arrival at home, [her] father could not open the front door because YY had locked it from the inside. He rang the bell and YY called the police because ‘there was an impostor outside the house who was picking the lock and pretending to be her father’. (Brighetti at al. 2007, p. 191)

 

Capgras is a monothematic delusion, a delusion whose content is restricted to a single topic, in this case the identity of YY's father.

In ‘Monothematic Delusions and the Limits of Rationality’ (published in the British Journal for the Philosophy of Science in 2021), we put forward a new account of such delusions. Our view is a version of the two-factor model according to which two factors are responsible for monothematic delusions (Davies et al. 2001). The first is a disruption in experience, e.g., a missing affective response to loved ones. The second is a cognitive impairment which inclines the subject towards delusional belief. This second factor distinguishes subjects with disordered experience but no delusion from subjects with disordered experience who form the delusion (Tranel et al. 1995).


Adam Bradley


We are motivated to develop a new view because we believe that existing theories do not satisfactorily explain why subjects initially entertain the delusional thought, e.g. "This person who looks like my father is an imposter" (Parrott 2016). The contents of most monothematic delusions are bizarre, and one wonders why subjects would even consider them, let alone believe them. A satisfactory account of monothematic delusions should help us understand this.

Existing two-factor views cannot explain the subject’s initial entertainment of the delusional thought because of their commitment to Maherian Rationality:

Maherian Rationality: The cognitive processes involved in delusion entertainment, adoption, and maintenance are of a generally rational kind whose operation is impaired in the domain of the delusion.

Traditional endorsement and explanationist views both seek to explain delusion formation on the model of rational belief-forming processes that have gone off the rails: either endorsement of the content of experience as a perceptual belief, or else an attempt to explain one’s disordered experience. But both endorsement and explanation are, in general, rational processes. So these views seek to explain delusion formation on the model of rational cognitive processes.


But the contents of monothematic delusions are typically so bizarre and that we must look beyond the rational faculties of the mind in order to explain them. When a subject with the Cotard delusion forms the belief that she is dead, she is not endorsing the content of experience or trying to explain anything. Instead, we argue, she is trying to express what her experience is like. Similarly, YY is not trying to explain bizarre experiential ‘data’, or taking on the content of her experience at face value. Instead, she is trying to articulate what her experience of her father is like.

The contents of monothematic delusions arise, then, not out of any rational process (not even a malfunctioning one), but from the sorts of processes involved in figurative thought and metaphorical language. There we have a rich repository of associations to draw on, associations which have already laid down ‘tracks’ in the mind along which thought naturally flows. 

 On our view, the delusional subject entertains thoughts like "I am dead" or "My wife has been replaced by an impostor" for the same reason that one might say "I am going to explode" as a way of describing their anger. We have a latent supply of figurative and metaphorical associations to draw on in thought and speech. These connections are already intelligible to us--we track them to understand poetry, for instance--but are not rational.

What is distinctive about the delusional subject is that she does not merely entertain such thoughts, she adopts them as beliefs. This calls for a second factor. Cotard delusion is typically thought to result from severe depression. But subjects who are not delusional express feelings of severe depression using terms such as ‘dead’ or ‘inanimate’ or ‘nonexistent’. A subject suffering from depersonalization may say: "I feel as if I am dead". The delusional subject, however, just thinks "I’m dead". They lose the ‘as if’ operator. 

We posit, therefore, that the second factor that causes the thought to become fixed as a delusion is a selective deficit in the subject’s capacity to understand figurative language as figurative in the domain of the delusion. As a result, delusional subjects come to confuse their figurative expressions of their experience for the literal truth.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...