Skip to main content

A Philosophy of Medicine Special Issue

This week on Imperfect Cognitions, we showcased a couple of posts by authors with papers published in a special issue from the European Journal of Analytic Philosophy (EuJAP). The special issue on the Philosophy of Medicine was guest-edited by Anke Bueter and Saana Jukola.

In this third and final post, the guest editors of the issue Anke and Saana give a summary of the special issue and the other papers included in it. Anke is an associate professor at Aarhus University. Her main research interests lie within feminist philosophy of science and philosophy of psychiatry. Saana is a post-doctoral researcher at the Ruhr-University Bochum. She is interested in the philosophy of medicine, social epistemology, and values in science.


Anke Bueter


Philosophy of medicine has become established as a distinct branch of philosophy relatively recently. Of course, philosophical questions concerning, for instance, the nature of disease or the ethical responsibilities of physicians are not new. However, less than 15 years ago it was possible to ask: “Does Philosophy of Medicine Exist?” (Marcum 2008, 3). Since then, the field of research has become increasingly independent from bioethics, philosophy of biology and other neighbouring subfields of philosophy. Philosophy of medicine now has professional associations, specialized journals, and textbooks. 

For the special issue on philosophy of medicine for the European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, we were particularly keen on receiving submissions investigating the interconnectedness of epistemic, metaphysical, ethical, and/or political aspects of medical research and practice. A major motivation for editing the special issue was the recognition that many of the critical philosophical questions that arise in the context of medicine and healthcare cannot be answered by drawing on just one philosophical tradition. 

For example, the current COVID-19 has clearly demonstrated how ethical and political considerations cannot be ignored when discussing what mitigation measures should be undertaken. In what follows, we briefly summarize the topics of the articles that appeared in this issue.


Saana Jukola


In their contribution “Diagnostic Justice: Testing for Covid-19” Ashley Graham Kennedy and Bryan Cwik discuss diagnostic testing. They argue that testing for COVID-19 has different goals depending on whether it is done for clinical care for individuals, as entry criterion to trials in clinical research, and in surveillance on population level. Each of these goals is connected to different epistemic challenges and moral obligations towards test subjects. 

Daria JadreÅ¡kić also looks at questions raised by the COVID-19 pandemic in her article “Adapt to Translate – Adaptive Clinical Trials and Biomedical Innovation”. Her focus is on clinical trials that have to be conducted under intense time pressure. JadreÅ¡kić argues that the validity of so-called adaptive trials has to be assessed on a case by case basis and with a focus on implemen­tation. 

In addition, she shows that adaptive trial design is not a novelty introduced by COVID-19 research, but can be placed within the larger context of the productivity crisis in pharmaceutical research and new developments in translational medicine.

In her article “Wrongful Medicalization and Epistemic Injustice in Psychiatry: The Case of Premenstrual Dysphoric Disorder”, Anne-Marie Gagne'-Julien shows how the framework of epistemic injustice can be applied to identifying problematic medicalization. 

She expands Kaczmarek's pragmatic account of medicalization by combining it with insights from theorizing on epistemic injustice and applies it to the case of "Premenstrual Dysphoric Disorder. According to her, this is a case of wrongful medicalization because the process of establishing the diagnosis was not adequately inclusive. You can read a blog post about her paper here

Jacob Stegenga’s contribution also deals with medicalization. The focus of his “Medicalization of Sexual Desire” is on low female sexual desire and the respective DSM diagnosis of “Female Sexual Interest/Arousal Disorder”. Stegenga analyses two conflicting perspectives on low female sexual desire: 

The so-called mainstream focuses on its biological underpinnings and considers it a genuine disease. The critical view, in turn, focuses on the social context and cultural factors that impact sexuality and respective ideas of normality. By examining arguments for both views, Stegenga suggests focusing on pragmatic considerations of the harms and benefits of medicalizing the condition.

Kathleen Murphy-Hollies’ paper “When a Hybrid Account of Disorder is not Enough: The Case of Gender Dysphoria” applies Jerome Wakefield’s concept of mental disorder as harmful dysfunction (HD). Murphy-Hollies argues that HD leaves the relation between its components (“harm” and “dysfunction”) undertheorized and, consequently, may lead to pathologization of normal states. 

Particularly in the case of gender dysphoria, assessing why purported dysfunctions are perceived as harmful and disvalued. This has two implications. Firstly, there is a distinction between sex dysphoria and gender dysphoria. Secondly, the legitimacy of the diagnosis of gender dysphoria depends on how we conceptualize gender in a sociological sense. You can read a blog post about her paper here.

In the final article of the special issue, “The Quantitative Problem for Theories of Dysfunction and Disease” Thomas Schramme addresses the issues of medicalization from a more general and conceptual angle. His focus is on the problem of how to draw a line between “functional” and “dysfunctional” traits. Schramme argues that this quantitative problem can be based on biological facts about goal-effectivity and does not require making value-laden judgments. 

Thus conceived, biological dysfunction is a necessary condition for a state or process to be a disease. Yet, it is not sufficient, as Schramme shows by introducing a distinction between biological and clinical dysfunction. While the identification of clinical dysfunction calls for evaluative and pragmatic considerations, the fact that it is based on empirical questions about biological functions helps to avoid over-medicalization, Schramme argues. 

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...