Skip to main content

False: How Mistrust, Disinformation, and Motivated Reasoning Make Us Believe Things That Aren’t True

In this post, Joe Pierre, professor of psychology at UC San Francisco, discusses his recently published book, False: How Mistrust, Disinformation, and Motivated Reasoning Make Us Believe Things That Aren’t True (OUP, 2025)


False



As a psychiatrist, my clinical work as a psychiatrist through the years has focused on the treatment of people with psychotic disorders. But in my academic work, I’ve been drawn to the grey area between psychopathology and normality and especially the continuum of delusion-like beliefs and full-blown delusions that includes religious, ideological, and conspiracy theory beliefs.

In psychiatry, false beliefs like cognitive distortions or delusions are typically chalked up to psychopathology. People have cognitive distortions because they have major depressive disorderand people are delusional because they have schizophrenia. And although research might tell us that delusional thinking can be attributed to anomalous subjective experiences or a “jumping to conclusions” cognitive style, those are ultimately considered to be part of the psychotic processes. One way or another then, false beliefs in psychiatry are explained by something going wrong in our brains.

And yet, we know all too well that false beliefs—including those that are sometimes held with unassailable, delusion-like conviction—are hardly limited to those with mental illness. Most of us hold some beliefs like that, whether they’re so-called positive illusions (e.g., the belief that we’re better than average), religious faiths, or political ideologies. But if we’re not mentally ill and such false beliefs are in fact normal, then we shouldn’t (and psychiatry doesn’t) use psychopathology to explain them away.

Much of my academic writing has been motivated by trying to resolve a question in my mind. And since I couldn’t find a good, “one-stop shopping” source of information on why normal people can hold so tenaciously to false beliefs, I decided to write a book about it myself. After several years of drafting and rewriting the text and finding a publisher in Oxford University press, I’m pleased to say that False: How Mistrust, Disinformation, and Motivated Reasoning Make Us Believe Things That Aren’t True was finally released in March 2025.

The book may as well have been entitled Imperfect Cognitions since it focuses on exactly that—the less-than-optimal cognitive processes that underlie false belief in normal people like you and me. It begins by covering ground that includes the false beliefs of mental illness like delusions and cognitive distortions, while drawing a clear line in the sand to help the reader distinguish between clinical delusions and mere delusion-like beliefs despite the temptation to conflate the two. It then moves on to the overconfidence of the Dunning-Kruger Effect and fallible memories, confirmation bias, and motivated reasoning before making its way to cognitive dissonance and bullshit receptivity.

In addition to such individual-level explanations, False sidesteps the fundamental attribution error to highlight social contributors to false belief including mistrust, misinformation, and the group identity aspects of motivated reasoning. While I sometimes refer to this as a “socio-epistemic” model, lately I’ve taken to calling it a “3M Model” (although the publisher didn’t like the alliteration and had me substitute “disinformation” for “misinformation” in the book’s subtitle). Whatever it’s called, it’s my opinion that emphasizing mistrust, misinformation, and motivated reasoning helps to provide a universal and normalizing framework to understand false belief in place of pejorative and wrongheaded claims that the world—or at least our ideological opposites—has fallen victim to the likes of mass delusion or mass psychosis.

Although False provides an overview of research on imperfect cognitions and is densely referenced (this seemed like a necessity for a book on false beliefs), it was written for the lay reader and is loaded with anecdotes to illustrate its points. In the second half, it tackles timely subjects like political polarization, morality, and climate change head on before concluding with recommendations for how to steer both individuals and societies away from believing things that aren’t true and acting upon false beliefs.

Unfortunately, it’s hard to argue that the world isn’t headed in exactly the wrong direction at the moment. Instead of moving closer to truth, belief in misinformation is running rampant, paving the way for authoritarian regimes to bulldoze democratic institutions with foolhardy political policies that are dismantling government services, defunding scientific research, and destroying public health networks and consumer protections.

In my obviously biased opinion as its author, False couldn’t be more relevant today, although part of me wishes that wasn’t the case. And yet, if we can better understand and appreciate why people so easily fall victim to misinformation and defend their false beliefs so passionately, then maybe it can help us work on solutions to get us back on track as individuals and as societies. With that in mind, if more people read False, it might become less relevant in the future. I hope that happens.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...