Skip to main content

Delusions as Malfunctioning Beliefs

Kengo Miyazono
with Charles Darwin
I am a research fellow at University of Birmingham and a JSPS (Japan Society for the Promotion of Science) fellow. My main research area is philosophy of mind, broadly construed (including philosophy of psychology, philosophy of psychiatry and early modern philosophy of mind). Recently, I am working on a project which is, directly or indirectly, related to epistemic innocence project.

The aim of this project is to present and develop a new strategy to defend doxasticism about delusion from the main argument against it. Doxasticism about delusion is the view that delusions are beliefs.

Although this view is widely accepted in psychiatry, there is a simple but powerful philosophical argument against it. I call it “the argument from causal role”.
- Playing a belief-like causal role is necessary for a mental state to be a belief.
- Many delusions fail to play belief-like causal roles.
- Therefore, many delusions are not beliefs.

The first premise directly comes from functionalism about belief, which is still the most popular view of belief. Second premise comes from clinical observations. It has been reported that, for instance, delusions are not very sensitive to evidence, they sometimes fail to guide non-verbal behavior, and they often fail to be coherent with other beliefs and emotions.

Many philosophers in the literature accept this argument and reject doxasticism (e.g. Gregory Currie, Andy Egan, Eric Schwitzgebel). Other philosophers resist the argument by rejecting the second premise (e.g. Lisa Bortolotti).


The main aim of this project is to explore the other option that has’t been (seriously) explored yet, namely, the option of resisting the argument by rejecting the first premise. I propose an alternative theory of belief according to which playing a belief-like causal role is not necessary for a mental state to be a belief. (See David Lewis on “mad pain” for a similar attempt.) The theory is a version of teleological theories of mind (e.g. Ruth Millikan) and it is called “teleo-attitude functionalism (TAF)”.

According to TAF, what is necessary and sufficient for a mental state to be a belief is to have the function of playing a belief-like causal role, not to actually play the role. And it is possible that a mental state has the function of playing a belief-like causal role without actually playing the role (= malfunctioning belief) for the same reason that, for instance, it is possible that a human organ has the function of pumping blood without actually doing it (=malfunctioning heart).

TAF rejects the first premise of the argument from causal role, because actually playing a belief-like causal role is not necessary for a mental state to be a belief according to the theory. Even if many delusions fail to actually play belief-like causal roles, it doesn’t rule out the possibility that they are nonetheless (malfunctioning) beliefs, for the same reason that even if a human organ fails to actually pump blood, it doesn’t rule out the possibility that it is nonetheless a (malfunctioning) heart.

I also argue for the following additional claims.


The major objections to TAF (e.g. Swampman objection) are not very persuasive and, thus, it is a good theory of belief. Under TAF, there are some reasons to favor doxasticism over other alternative views such as imagination-view (Currie) or bimagination-view (Egan).

The idea that delusions are malfunctioning beliefs is helpful in explaining the fact that delusions are pathological phenomena, especially when the idea is combined with the influential view, proposed and defended by Jerome Wakefield, that harmful malfunctioning is the essential feature of disorder.
TAF can be generalized and applicable to other kinds of mental states such as desires, emotions or moods. In doing so, we can conceptualize other (symptoms of) mental disorders as other instances of malfunctioning mental states. For instance, pathological anxiety in anxiety disorder can be conceptualized as malfunctioning anxiety.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...