Skip to main content

Against Doxastic Theories of Delusion


Are delusions beliefs?
Delusions are formed in response to perceptual or sensory experiences, they interact with other mental states in a more or less intelligible fashion and they regulate behavior. Any mental state with these properties deserves to be called a belief, or so say doxastic theorists of delusion. The fact that delusions are irrational merely means that we need to search for the causes of irrationality rather than abandon the doxastic conception.

I disagree. Delusions also have some very un-belief like features. They are very resistant to counterevidence, often maintained with ambivalence, and also seem to involve a phenomenology and stance towards the world which is very dissimilar to that of someone trying to produce and verify an empirical hypothesis. John Nash the Fields medal winner (the Nobel prize for mathematics) and celebrity schizophrenic said of his delusions “ it’s kind of like a dream. In a dream it’s typical not to be rational.” Adoxastic theorists have variously argued that delusions while they have some belief like properties (as do dreams) are better conceived of as imaginary states or a distinctive type of propositional attitude.

The debate over the nature of delusion is complicated by the fact that there is no agreed standard for how much departure from canonical standards of rationality is required before we philosophers withdraw the doxastic appellation controllee “belief” and call the state something else. Thus delusions are rational irrational or arational depending on your standards.

This confusion is of no help to psychologists, clinicians and neuroscientists who discover correlates of delusion such as unusual patterns of brain activity, lapses of working memory, unusual distributions of dopamine receptors or synaptic processing irregularities. Are these the substrates of belief fixation according to principles of rational inference, or some other cognitive process?

I think we have the problem the wrong way round. I think we should take the advice of Dominic Murphy and let the cognitive neuroscience determine our characterization of psychiatric disorder in general and delusion in particular. The basic idea is that we determine the cognitive properties of the neural systems involved in a particular disorder and phrase the explanation in terms of cognitive processes. This does not mean dispensing with personal level vocabulary provided that that vocabulary reflects or can be smoothly mapped to the best cognitive theory.

For how to do the mapping I recommend the interventionist methodology described by Carl Craver in Explaining the Brain. (Another version is provided by John Campbell’s work on control variables). The basic idea is that we have a good explanation when we can predictably intervene and manipulate components of a system (in this case the mind). To do this we need to have a good understanding of the basic mechanisms which comprise it. Both these desiderata are absent from characterisations of psychiatric illness which invest in doxastic terminology. The whole point of a notion like “belief” is that it abstracts entirely from cognitive and neural processes.

Consider psychiatric cases like Borderline Personality or Post Traumatic Stress Disorder that produce a range of symptoms. The best way to understand what is going on in these cases is to understand the way basic mechanisms of emotional regulation function under different conditions (adversity in infancy that disrupts attachment, violence and trauma) and interact with cognitive processes. A label like emotional dysregulation is more helpful than “borderline personality” precisely because it directs us to the functioning of systems that produce the symptoms. PTSD is a rare case of a psychiatric classification which has the potential to allow different levels of explanation from neural to personal to be integrated via cognitive theory.

If we think of delusions as beliefs then such integrative explanation becomes impossible, precisely because the concept of belief abstracts away from mechanistic explanation. I prefer to think of delusions as instances of unsupervised activity in the default network triggered and or maintained by hypersalient experience. The cognitive properties of the default network explain the patterns of experience and thought characteristic of delusion.


A more detailed explanation is in my paper Delusional Attitudes and Default Thinking. An even more detailed explanation is in my Measure of Madness: Delusions, Philosophy and Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, out next year with MIT Press. And this is my website.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph