Skip to main content

Why can’t we think of mental disorders as being mental?

This post is by Matthew Broome.

Matthew Broome
I’ve recently taken up a new post as Senior Clinical Research Fellow in the Department of Psychiatry at the University of Oxford, but prior to that was Associate Clinical Professor of Psychiatry at Warwick University and Lecturer at the Institute of Psychiatry, King’s College London, and it was during a Journal Club at the IoP where I first met Lisa Bortolotti and we began our collaboration.

A month ago I was delighted to take part in a public philosophy event at the European Institute of the LSE, as part of their Consilience series, devoted to mental illness.  The format was that, together with two colleagues, Tim Thornton and Bonnie Evans, we were asked to talk about the nature of mental illness prior to the chair, Kristina Musholt, opening the discussion to the floor.  

The event came slightly prior to the publication of the DSM 5 and I opened by starting with the definition of mental disorder, which is:
‘a behavioral or psychological syndrome or pattern that reflects an underlying psychobiological dysfunction. Consequences of which are clinically significant distress or disability that must not be merely expectable response to common stressors and losses, a culturally sanctioned response to a particular event, or a result of social deviance or conflicts with society’ (APA, 2013).
In papers, Lisa and I have explored ways in which mental disorders have been conceptualized (Broome 2006Bortolotti and Broome 2009Broome and Bortolotti 2010), including pragmatic and instrumental conceptions, biological realist conceptions as well as eliminativist positions. After briefly reviewing these, I summarized the empirical data we had from psychiatrists themselves demonstrating the heterogeneity of their views regarding mental disorders (Harland et al., 2009).  Against this background, I then tried to defend the view that we can have an idea of disorder in the realm of the mental without being dualists and without having to feel pressure to reduce or translate this conception wholly into neuroscience, and drew on issues of normativity, both epistemic and moral, that have been suggested to be integral to the definition of key features of psychopathology, such as delusions and personality disorder.

In parallel, and with colleagues at the Maudsley Philosophy Group, we have tried to archive and re-introduce to contemporary psychiatry ‘thick’ detailed descriptions of mental disorder that may expand the ways philosophers can think of the normative elements that may describe mental disorder most accurately, and  are in turn, the elements that make such mental states disordered.  For example, a type of interpersonal interaction in personality disorder, a manner of reason-giving and justification in delusions.

This culminated in the publication of The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological Psychiatry, a book that collects many important phenomenological accounts of mental disorder including schizophrenia, mania, depression, and obsessive-compulsive disorder. 2013 also marks the centenary of the publication of Karl Jaspers’ General Psychopathology and many of these themes will be explored more fully in a one-day conference celebrating this publication at the Royal Society of Medicine in October 2013. 

Hope to see you there!

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. TrĂ©molière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...