Skip to main content

Epistemic Innocence (part 2)

This post is by Ema Sullivan-Bissett.



In her last post, Lisa outlined two conditions on Epistemic Innocence: 

1. Epistemic Benefit. The cognition delivers some significant epistemic benefit to a given subject at a given time, that is, it contributes to the acquisition, retention or use of relevant true beliefs.


2. No Relevant Alternatives. Alternative cognitions to the imperfect cognition are either unavailable or fail to deliver the same epistemic benefits as the imperfect cognition to that subject at that time.

In this post I will focus on the second condition, which requires further elucidation with respect to what notion of unavailability is in play. 



We might usefully distinguish three kinds of unavailability which can be incorporated into the No Relevant Alternatives condition, and what kind is at play will depend on the case. 

The first notion of unavailability is strong unavailability, such that what it means to say that an alternative cognition is unavailable is exactly that—there is no way the subject can gain access to the alternative cognition, alternative cognitions, or information which would suggest them, are introspectively and otherwise unavailable to the subject. The notion of strong unavailability might be in play when we are thinking about cases of distorted memory due to neurological damage. 

For example, consider Lisa’s case of a dementia patient who claims to remember going to the beach with her parents that morning, but the trip she recalls occurred when she was a teenager, sixty years ago. A memory of the trip which included the correct time at which it took place, or information which would suggest to the subject that she had made a mistake with respect to the time of the trip, is strongly unavailable to the subject due to the severe memory impairment she suffers as a result of her dementia. 

The second kind of unavailability which might figure in the No Relevant Alternatives condition is motivational unavailability.  If the motivation for retaining a cognition is sufficiently strong, alternative cognitions are motivationally unavailable to the subject. Confabulatory explanations and self-deceptive beliefs meet the No Relevant Alternatives condition in that alternative explanations are unavailable to the subject in this sense of unavailability. 

If I suddenly cross the road upon seeing a black man, my action might be guided by implicit biases against certain racial groups. I might confabulate to explain my behaviour by saying that I needed to cross the road because I mistakenly thought I saw a friend on the other side. Here I offer a confabulatory explanation of my action. Because I like to think of myself as person of egalitarian persuasion, who does not have racial prejudices, the explanation of my behaviour which cites implicit biases against these groups is motivationally unavailable to me. 

Or take the case of the cuckholded husband who self-deceptively believes that his wife is faithful. Evidence that she is unfaithful may be available to him (insofar as it is perceptually available—he sees that his wife returns home late, dishevelled, and uninterested in him), but an alternative cognition, such as the belief that his wife is having an affair, is motivationally unavailable, due to the husband’s very strong desire for it to be the case that his wife is faithful. 

The third kind of unavailability is explanatory unavailability, which is cashed out in terms of the implausibility or poor explanatory power of alternative cognitions (by the subject’s lights). A subject may come to have a cognition which explains some experience she has. If alternative cognitions which might also be candidate explanations for her experiences are such that they strike her as seriously implausible or explanatorily inadequate, these alternative cognitions are explanatorily unavailable

Consider an instance of non-pathological belief formation: there are bite marks in my cheese, I hear scratching at night, and my cat is agitated. I come to the conclusion that I have mice in my house. An alternative explanation might be that cheese-eating, cat-hating, noisy fairies are infiltrating my home at night. This explanation is not available to me in the sense I have in mind here due to the incredulity I would feel towards it. It is either not considered by me, or it is such that I rule it out on grounds of implausibility or poor explanatory power, relative to the preferred and adopted cognition. 

I think that delusional beliefs sometimes meet the No Relevant Alternatives condition for epistemic innocence in virtue of alternative cognitions being explanatorily unavailable—I will write about this in my next post.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...