Skip to main content

Ownership and Thought Insertion

This post is by Rachel Gunn, PhD student at the University of Birmingham, working on delusion and thought insertion.

After introducing the phenomenon of thought insertion in my previous post, here I discuss ownership of thoughts. The impossibility of immunity to error through misidentification (IEM) is an established notion in relation to the self. If I have something to say about my experience it is self-evident that I am the one undergoing the experience. I cannot be mistaken. 

A subject experiencing thought insertion cannot be mistaken about who is experiencing the thought. Whilst this is true it does not explain what the experience is like. The thought is observed or witnessed by the subject, they have access to the content and have some sort of first-person experience of it. It is not, however, the same kind of experience that they ‘normally’ have. It differs from other thoughts – but in what sense?




A close look at the definition and at the phenomenology repeatedly highlights the sense in which the thought feels as if it is given to the subject fully formed and therefore not generated by the subject. In other words there is a lack of agency regarding the thought. However, a lack of agency does not seem sufficient to differentiate between other kinds of thoughts and thought insertion as described by the subject. After all, I have thoughts all the time that are not self-consciously generated – they just ‘pop’ into my head. I might sometimes wonder where the thought came from and it may appear to lack agency in some sense but I never have cause to deny that the thought is mine.

When experiencing thought insertion the subject passively observes a thought that has appeared to them from ‘outside’ and feels no sense of ownership of the thought. Alienonite (on the crazyboard website) describes her experience as “…thoughts that do not ‘feel’ like my own…”, Deli on Psychcentral says “I have heard voices before… it was very easy to identify that those thoughts belonged to another person – I wasn’t being forced to think them myself, just listen to them…” and Marion Aslan described a voice that was “…inside my head, though I knew it not to be me or my own thoughts…” (Aslan in Romme et al. 2009, p.238).

In their review article on thought insertion Simon Mullins and Sean Spence distinguished the phenomenon from other thought disorders through differences in ‘thought possession’. For thought insertion the ego boundary is intruded upon and the ownership of the thought is alien. For other phenomena, such as influenced thinking, thought withdrawal and obsessional thinking, the thought is owned by the subject. Waters and Badcock argue that there is good evidence that first-rank symptoms (all forms of passivity phenomena) do not selectively suggest a lack of agency. It is possible that ownership and agency are highly complex overlapping experiences and that they may not be easy to separate where passivity phenomena are concerned.

Looking at the evidence it seems that thought insertion proper is a passive, observational experience of a thought perceived by the subject to be different in kind from their usual thought experiences and identified as a thought ‘projected’ into the mind of the subject where the sense of producing the thought (agency and authorship) and the sense that the thought belongs to the subject (ownership) are both lacking.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph