Skip to main content

Emotional Actions


This post is by Mary Carman (pictured above), who will be joining Thumos, the Genevan Research Group on Emotions, Values and Norms as a Postdoctoral Research Fellow in April. Mary works on emotions and action, and as part of her previous Postdoctoral Fellowship at the University of Witwatersrand, South Africa, she started working on topics in Bioethics. In this post, she writes about the rational role in action emotions can play.

In my PhD thesis and a paper currently under review, I develop an account of emotional actions that gives emotion a rational role in action. In this brief post, I outline how such an account might look.

Let’s start with an example of an impulsive emotional action from Elisabeth Pacherie (2002): I am fearfully running away from a bear, spot a crack in the rocks too narrow for the bear to fit, and climb through. In such cases, we act on the basis of an emotion without first forming beliefs and desires related to what to do. These actions can be under our control, in execution if not in initiation, and we have at least a de re awareness of what we are doing and why. And, often, such actions are in line with what we would take to be reasons favouring the action if we had deliberated more fully. Superficially, then, many of these actions are candidates for rational action (see another paper under review).

Now, acting rationally is traditionally thought to require that we act on beliefs and desires related to some goal we aim to achieve with the action. If one form or another of this picture is correct, then these emotional actions are not rational. This traditional picture, however, fails to take into account certain things we now know about emotion.

For one thing, emotions are fundamental to our functional practical rationality, and they have pervasive effects not only on our actions but also on our thoughts and decision-making. For another, emotions aren’t blind responses to just anything. They are responses to things of putative significance to us in our environment. They are also not complexes of beliefs and desires as once thought, although they are intentional states. And a substantial philosophical literature has developed in support of the claim that emotions can even provide reasons.

These points, together with other challenges to the traditional picture, all support taking seriously the idea that emotion can have a role not only in our functional practical rationality, but also in our conception of rational agency.

How, then, can we go about creating space in a theory of rational action for these emotional actions?

One thing the traditional picture captures well is the idea that acting rationally requires that we have some kind of control over what we are doing, and that we guide our actions in response to reasons as reasons. Can we guide our action in a rationally meaningful way when acting on the basis of an emotion? I argue that we can.

Specifically, I argue that an agent can: (a) be aware of the emotional considerations at the time of acting, given the intentional nature of emotions; (b) be aware of them as counting in favour of her action; and, (c) offer them as reasons that rationalise her action.

I’ll focus on (b) for the remainder of this post.

As mentioned above, emotions are responses to things of putative significance to us. What is of significance to us is grounded in what cares and concerns we have. Indeed, the subject’s cares and concerns are central to many accounts of emotions, both in psychology and philosophy. So, through being grounded in cares and concerns, emotions can motivate behavioural responses to things of significance to us, for both agents and non-agents.

Agents, however, are also capable of identifying with their cares. As a default, a caring agent will experience an emotional response as a manifestation of her caring. (She may not reflectively identify with that care, an issue I address in my paper.) Through that caring, I argue, she takes the way things appear seriously because of their significance, relative to caring. And, while not a truth-attitude like belief, her emotional awareness is sufficient for being an awareness of the emotional considerations as counting in favour of action that protects those cares.

The basic idea is thus that emotions can have a rational role in action because the way we are committed to how things appear emotionally, via caring, allows us to guide our actions by the reason-giving considerations we take ourselves to have. Of course, this is a controversial claim and I have only briefly described one aspect of an account that continues to develop.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...