Skip to main content

Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Contemporary Introduction

Today's post is by Sam Wilkinson (University of Exeter) on his recent book Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Contemporary Introduction (2023, Routledge).


When I started teaching philosophy of psychiatry about ten years ago I noticed that, while there was plenty of literature out of which a well-structured and coherent course could be built, there was (to my knowledge) no single textbook around which to base one. 

Year-on-year, as my module was tweaked and improved, largely thanks to feedback from my students, it occurred to me (wrongly, as it turns out) that it would be relatively straightforward to turn said module into a textbook. And that’s what I’ve done - eventually!

Like the module itself, the textbook is divided into two parts, which reflect two quite different enterprises that fall under the category “philosophy of psychiatry”. 

The first enterprise involves philosophical scrutiny of psychiatry, with “psychiatry” here including both psychiatric practice and psychiatric research. The second involves philosophical engagement with the psychiatric phenomena themselves. In light of this, Part 1 is called “Philosophy of Psychiatric Practice and Research” while Part 2 is called “Philosophy and Psychopathology”.

After an overarching introduction entitled “What is philosophy of psychiatry and why does it matter?” (Chapter 1), Part 1 begins by reflecting on the purview of psychiatry (Chapter 2), addressing different approaches to the nature of mental illness, including challenges to its very existence and, by extension, to the legitimacy of psychiatry as a discipline. Then, Chapter 3 addresses issues surrounding the “medical model” and whether psychiatry ought to proceed via diagnosis. 

Chapter 4 (“Mental illness, moral responsibility, and the boundaries of the person”) addresses questions about the way in which psychiatric conditions can impact on our autonomy, moral responsibility and sense of self. Different views about this can be seen as either tangential or central to questions about the fundamental nature of mental illness. (Viewed as central, to say that someone suffers from mental illness is, in part, to say that they are a passive victim of a condition.)

The role of culture in our thinking about pathology is addressed in Chapter 5, with religion as a salient test case. One important distinction here is between the context of formation and the context of evaluation. The former denotes the way in which culture may impact on the presence or prevalence of certain problematic phenomena, whereas the latter denotes the way in which culture impacts on the way in which certain phenomena are evaluated as pathological or otherwise. These two often interact in interesting ways.

The final chapter of Part 1 (Chapter 6) applies thinking in philosophy of science on the nature of explanation to the issue of scientific explanation in psychiatry. What is it to properly scientifically explain a phenomenon of psychiatric interest? A broad family of “pragmatic” views is presented in a particularly sympathetic light.

Sam Wilkinson

Part 2 can be more swiftly summarized. It goes through various phenomena of psychiatric interest, trying to shed light on what they are and what philosophical issues they raise. So, Chapter 7 examines schizophrenia, and some important controversies that arise when thinking about that concept, and how that concept is not simply a different concept, but a different kind of concept, from that of psychosis. Building on this, Chapters 8 and 9 examine voice hearing and delusions, respectively. The former touches on various issues, including the nature of perceptual experience and inner speech. The latter touches especially on the nature and norms of belief. 

Chapters 10 and 11 discuss depression and addiction. One of the big challenges surrounding depression concerns how we are to delineate depression as a clinical phenomenon. In turn, addiction raises fundamental questions about the nature of motivation, rationality and internal conflict.

The final chapter concerns my hopes and predictions for the future of the discipline. This involves discussion of i) overlooked phenomena that have received some philosophical scrutiny but would benefit from more (e.g. PTSD, personality disorders), ii) mental health in the digital age, iii) the exciting field of computational psychiatry, iv) approaches to mental health that might be called “externalistic”, and v) innovative approaches to psychiatric discourse.

Finally, I’d like to say a bit about how the book is written and its aims. Clearly one thing that lecturers avoid is a straight-up presentation of the canonical literature (“So-and-so said such-and-such”). What I’ve tried to do, with this book, is introduce each topic in an intuitive and relatable way that makes it clear what philosophical itches there are to scratch. That way, when the existing work is presented, the reader can see what exactly it is in the service of.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph