Skip to main content

Responsibility without Blame for Psychopathy: A Utopia?

This post is by Olivia Siegfried, currently studying for a Master’s degree in the School of Psychology at the University of Birmingham. Olivia is interested in youth mental health, personality disorders, and forensic psychology, and adopts a social constructionist perspective to understand these issues.

This is part of a series of posts by students of the Philosophy and Ethics of Mental Health and Wellbeing module at the Institute for Mental Health. They share some of their views on key topics discussed in the module.

Olivia Siegfried

Responsibility without blame

As personality disorders are notoriously hard to treat, Hannah Pickard has put forward the ‘responsibility without blame’ approach (Pickard, 2011) for clinicians to adopt to foster the best clinical outcomes. Although sounding inherently paradoxical, we can hold people responsible without blaming them by segregating responsibility from morality and instead defining it through a person’s agency. 

Taking responsibility for their actions allows patients to own their behaviour and emotions and provides them with the foundation to make changes in the future. Blaming them, however, strips them of their agency and encourages therapeutic nihilism. 

Pickard advocates for clinicians to treat people with compassion and view adverse behaviour as the result of great psychological distress. She emphasises that considering the patient’s history of trauma (which is common in people with personality disorders) allows for this compassion to develop, which in turn counteracts the impulse to blame. 

People with antisocial personality disorder (Fisher and Hany, 2019) who possess high levels of antagonistic personality traits (e.g. callousness) come closest to our understanding of a ‘psychopath’. I will outline here how psychopaths differ from other personality disorder patients and thereby put into question the viability of the ‘responsibility without blame’ approach for cases of psychopathy.

Trauma?

According to the ‘responsibility without blame’ framework, clinical compassion is fostered through understanding a patient’s behaviour as the result of severe psychological distress stemming from past traumatic environments. 

However, not all psychopaths have experienced trauma in their lives. Blair and colleagues (2006) argue that psychopathy predominantly arises through genetic pathways, and is less closely linked to social environments. For example, a twin study (Viding et al., 2008) found that the heritability of antisocial behaviour for children with co-occurring callous-unemotional traits was far greater than for those without them. 

Furthermore, the reactive aggression observed in other personality disorders is not always mirrored in psychopaths. They tend to demonstrate instrumental aggression (Blair et al., 2006) which is motivated by egocentric goals rather than being the result of hypervigilance. 

Thus, it is hard to envision how clinicians can adopt a compassionate approach to psychopaths’ aggressive behaviour if it does not constitute a coping mechanism for psychological distress stemming from trauma.

Aggression in psychopaths is more goal-directed. 

Prospection?

Neil Levy (2013) argues that psychopaths show impairments in mental time travel. This means that their ability to visualise themselves in past or future environments is diminished. 

The present is more salient to them, which is demonstrated through their nomadic lifestyle and ever-changing relationships. Thus, the DSM-5 (American Psychiatric Association, 2013) has included impulsivity and irresponsibility as diagnostic criteria for APD. Moreover, ‘temporal inefficacy’ (Petrican and Burris, 2011), a construct characterised by displeasure about the passing of linear time is associated with a reduced capacity for mental time travel and greater levels of psychopathic traits. 

Pickard states that holding patients responsible provides them with the agency to make future changes. However, this approach is unlikely to have the same merit for psychopaths who lack such prospection.

Psychopaths have difficulties looking into the future

In conclusion, the ‘responsibility without blame’ approach may be inappropriate for psychopaths, as they lack the personality disorder characteristics that the framework assumes. Although blaming them is unlikely to be the answer, it is important to be aware of these differences between personality disorders.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...