Skip to main content

Schizophrenia as a Disorder of Self, and Clinical Practice

Today's post is by Nimra Ahsan. Nimra is a fifth year medical student at the University of Birmingham, where she is currently completing a Masters in Mental Health. She is interested in how the study of mental health can help inform and improve future clinical practice, including her own. This is the last post in a series of perspectives from students taking the Philosophy and Ethics of Mental Health and Wellbeing module.

Nimra Ahsan


The interaction between psychiatry and psychopathology is one that is blending (Stanghellini and Broome, 2014). With a contemporary focus on patient experience, human subjectivity (or phenomenology) is creating a holistic perspective concerning mental health conditions, such as schizophrenia. Described as a ‘disturbance of minimal self’, our understanding of schizophrenia has deepened and the ipseity-disturbance model developed by Sass and Parnas has contributed to this substantially (Nelson, Parnas and Sass, 2014).





This model led to the formation of a symptom checklist, the Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience (EASE), which explores a patient’s ‘experiential or subjective anomalies’ in a semi-structured interview (Parnas et al, 2005). Built upon a Husserlian approach to phenomenology, this tool was established through descriptions from patients with schizophrenia spectrum disorders which collectively have an altered sense of self to help identify experiences of self-disturbance. However, it cannot be used alone diagnostically and does not yet include a comprehensive basis of anomalous experiences.

Regardless, research has shown that EASE not only demarcates schizophrenia from other disorders (Parnas and Henriksen, 2014), but could enable early recognition of self-disturbances and become a useful prognostic tool in those of clinical high risk (Værnes et al, 2021). Furthermore, in assessing basic self-disturbances, it was shown to aid detection of those at higher risk of non-remission or deterioration.

This study conducted by Værnes et al (2021) demonstrated that after one year of follow-up, increased levels of basic self-disturbances correlated with higher baseline levels (assessed using EASE) and were linked ‘with higher severity of positive, negative, disorganisation and general symptoms, and with a lower level of global functioning’. Additionally, a recent meta-analysis utilising EASE, concluded that self-disorders are specific to schizophrenia spectrum disorders, encouraging the idea that it should be considered a core clinical feature of schizophrenia (Burgin, Reniers and Humpston, 2022).

There have long been calls for diagnostic classification systems, such as the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM) and the International Classification of Diseases (ICD), to revise their definitions and symptomology to include the patient’s subjective experience in order to curate a person-centred approach to diagnosis (Irarrázaval, 2015). The aforementioned developments in our understanding of schizophrenia further reinforce this notion; hence, these significant advances should be incorporated into clinical practice to help better treat those with schizophrenia. 



Understanding this disturbance of self and the way in which patients perceive the world can help clinicians to accept the conflict of realities between themselves and the patient. An emphasis should be placed on ‘recovery of the patient’s sense of unity with himself when rebuilding his capacity of doing and being’, allowing patients to lead fulfilling lives alongside their symptoms through repairing their sense of self (Irarrázaval, 2013). It is now incredibly important for clinicians to comprehend and apply this phenomenological approach to schizophrenia – in doing so, patients may gain a deeper understanding of their condition, empowering them, which in turn can ‘alleviate self-stigmatisation, diminish guardedness, and equip patients with better coping mechanisms’ (Humpston and Broome, 2020).

Psychotherapeutic approaches need to be developed based upon the ‘recognition of the self-disorders’ crucial importance in the patient’s life-world’, for example, through an emphasis on psychoeducation (Nordgaard, 2021). The use of psychopharmacology may aid management of symptoms, but approaches need to focus on empathetic understanding and open, effective communication between clinicians and patients, rather than correction of perception and thought (Wilson, Humpston and Nathan, 2021). Clearly, human subjectivity needs to be at the forefront of the management of schizophrenia.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...