Skip to main content

Different Conceptions of Bias

Katherine Puddifoot has recently edited a special issue of Philosophical Psychology on bias. In this post, she introduces some of the conceptions of bias and discrimination discussed by the contributors. In next week's post Katherine will summarise the authors' ideas about how to mitigate bias.


Katherine Puddifoot

Ema Sullivan-Bissett provides a defence of her view that implicit biases are unconscious imaginings, by drawing on studies of the impact of the use of virtual reality on people’s biases. Sullivan-Bissett argues that implicit biases are not necessarily propositional, but may instead be characterized by being imagistic, explaining how sometimes, but not always, immersion in an imagistic virtual reality is effective in shifting bias.


Felipe de Carvalho and Joel Krueger adopt a conception of implicit bias as embodied perceptual habits. They argue that conceived in this way implicit bias can explain certain injustices experienced by children with Down syndrome and autism. Children experience maladaptive development niches due to the embodied perceptual habits of those around them, including their caregivers. 

Ella Whiteley focuses instead on a form of discrimination that happens via attention, “wherein certain social groups have the ‘wrong’ property (such as their skin color) attended to relatively better than the ‘right’ property (such as their accomplishments)”. Whiteley focuses on the importance of drawing on testimony from lived experience to understand this distinctive form of unintentional discrimination.

William Fraker discusses generics like “women are emotional”, proposing that they are dichotomizing perspectives, leading people to be viewed in terms of their distinction from others. Generics, on this view, can lead to unintentional discrimination by shaping behaviours and social expectations, and providing support for explanations and defences of these behaviours and expectations. 

Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Søren Serritzlew, Lasse Laustsen, Simone Sommer Degn and Andreas Albertsen are interested in how to conceptualize discrimination in general. In their experimental study, they probe whether discrimination tends to be conceived in a comparative and/or reflexive way. People are less likely to perceive discrimination where there is someone else similarly qualified who is treated differently from those who may have been discriminated against. However, as hypothesized, whether the social identity of the person who is treated differently is the same as that of the target person seems to matter.


Gabbrielle Johnson


Gabbrielle M Johnson focuses on ways that social bias can manifest in perception and cognition. Johnson argues that social biases should be defined as a response to the underdetermination of data. They take as an input particular instances of a social kind and produce a stereotypical property attribution. Social kind bias include perceptual biases and essentialising cognitive biases, which should be evaluated on different bases.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph