Skip to main content

On Epistemic Freedom and Epistemic Injustice

Today's post is from Karl Landström on his paper 'On Epistemic Freedom and Epistemic Injustice', recently published in Inquiry.



Karl Landström


‘Seek ye epistemic freedom first’ is how Sabelo Ndlovu-Gatsheni begins his book Epistemic Freedom in Africa: Deprovincialization and Decolonization (2018, 1). Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s book is a detailed study of the politics of knowing and knowledge production with emphasis on what he calls ‘the African struggle for epistemic freedom’. He locates the struggle for epistemic freedom in the continued entrapment of knowledge production in Africa within colonial, Euro- and North America-centric matrices of power. 

The central contribution of the book is the development of a general account of epistemic freedom. For Ndlovu-Gatsheni, epistemic freedom entails the right to think, theorise and develop one’s own methodologies to interpret the world, and write from where one is located unencumbered by Eurocentrism. Further, he argues that questions of epistemic freedom stand in direct relation to cognitive justice. That is, proper recognition of the diverse ways of knowing by which humans from across the globe makes sense of their experiences.

In my article, I examine the relationship between Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s account of epistemic freedom and a different set of theories pertaining to justice and injustice in our epistemic lives, namely those of epistemic injustice (Fricker 2007) and epistemic oppression (Dotson 2014) developed in analytic feminist epistemology. I argue that we ought to think of the relationship between epistemic freedom and epistemic injustice and oppression in two closely related ways. One which centres epistemic injustice and oppression as infringements on epistemic freedom, and one which centres the ameliorative role of epistemic freedom in redressing and eliminating existing epistemic injustice and oppression. 

For example, Emmalon Davis (2021) has argued that epistemic injustices introduce barriers to the participation in particular epistemic communities for the victims, which I contend ought to be thought of as type of infringement on epistemic freedom. The ameliorative role of epistemic freedom has been emphasised by Veli Mitova (2020) who position the epistemic freedom of the subjects of epistemic oppression as a key dimension in the struggles against the coloniality of knowledge and existing epistemic oppression. 

Being epistemically free would allow the subjects of oppression and coloniality to pursue their own epistemic agendas and projects, and thus offer a potential path to redress. Beyond these direct links between epistemic freedom and epistemic injustice and oppression, the different sets of theory share a number further intersections and further concerns. These include for example silencing, wilful ignorance and close-mindedness, and epistemic exploitation as widespread ethical, political and epistemic problems.

Lastly, I draw on the literature on epistemic oppression to sharpen Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s (2018) general conception of epistemic freedom, and I develop a tripartite structure for what substantial epistemic freedom entails. On my account, being epistemically free entails being able to choose the aims and methods of one’s epistemic endeavours and having the ability and freedom to pursue them. Further, being epistemically free requires the ability to freely and meaningfully partake in the epistemic communities that one belongs to and gaining appropriate uptake when doing so. 

This more nuanced conception of epistemic freedom accounts for the many different factors that can infringe upon one’s epistemic freedom to differing degrees, while at the same time preserving the original emphasis and strengths of Ndlovu-Gatsheni’s (2018) conception. 

As the literatures on epistemic decolonisation, epistemic injustice and oppression illustrate, structural, material, social and political factors all can limit one’s ability to pursue the epistemic endeavours of one’s choosing and one’s ability to meaningfully contribute to the epistemic communities one is a member of. Thus, the manner in which we conceive of epistemic freedom ought to reflect that complexity.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...