Skip to main content

What is it to imagine an emotion?

Today's post is by Radu Bumbăcea on his recently published paper "Imagining Emotions" (Erkenntnis).


Radu Bumbăcea


We all want to understand other people, and a central part of this understanding involves imagining their emotions ‘from the inside’. A key idea in the philosophy of emotions is that an emotion modifies the emoter’s experience of its object, that the emotion ‘colours’ the world: someone who is afraid of a dog experiences that dog as fearsome. In imagining an emotion E, therefore, the imaginer is supposed to gain some access into how the world is coloured by emotion E without having E oneself.

So far, the main approach to imagining emotions has been the simulationist one. According to such an approach, imagining an emotion is essentially having that emotion offline. In further metaphorical terms, we can say that imagining an emotion would involve building in one’s mind a copy of that emotion that is somehow marked as not-the-real-thing. 

This idea is often but not necessarily related to the broader view that we can run usual mental processes offline, and that many mental states have simulated equivalents. While a normal mental process involves believing that there is chocolate on the table, desiring chocolate, getting it and then feeling happy about this, the offline version would involve s-believing that there is chocolate, s-desiring it, having some representation of our getting it and then experiencing s-happiness.

I have a few worries about the simulationist view of imagining emotions. First, the mental state of simulating an emotion, as it is typically construed by simulationists, is very similar to that of having the emotion. Indeed, some go as far as to claim that simulated emotions just are emotions directed at an imagined scenario

Yet very often, for instance when we imagine an emotion of someone very different from us, we do not evaluate the world according to that emotion. I can imagine admiration for a dictator, but without taking the dictator as admirable. It follows that in imagining an emotion, we experience that emotion as ‘distant’ from us, and so the state of imagination is not too similar, let alone identical, to the state of that emotion. A second worry is that if we try to simulate the emotion of another person X, we essentially first build a copy in us and then attribute it to X. But this sounds incorrect: the attribution of the emotion to X is part of the mental state not an ulterior decision – we imagine the emotion E as X’s.

Rejecting simulationism about imagining emotions, I put in its stead the thesis that, rather than being a copy of an emotion E, imagining E is a representation of that emotion. The challenge is to show how this allows to understand the emotion ‘from the inside’. To start with, we need to distinguish between thin and thick representations. A thin representation merely refers to an object – think of the word ‘cat’ or of a belief about a cat. 

By contrast, a thick representation gives some access to the qualities of the represented object – here, think of a picture of a cat or a mental image of the cat. My claim is then that we can extend this to representations of mental states: I can form a belief about an emotion (‘X has emotion E’), but I can also form a thick representation of that emotion in my mind. This representation allows me to gain access to the phenomenal properties of E while experiencing E as not-my-emotion, as kept at a distance, as it were.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...