This post is by Sarah Robins (pictured above), an Assistant Professor of
Philosophy and affiliate member of the Cognitive and Brain Sciences Program in
Psychology at the University of Kansas. Her research is at the intersection of philosophy
and psychology, with a primary focus on memory. In this post she summarises her
recent paper ‘Misremembering’,
published in Philosophical Psychology.
Thanks, Ema, for the invitation to talk
about my recent paper ‘Misremembering’ with
Imperfect Cognitions readers.
The paper began from my fascination with
one of the most common experimental techniques for eliciting memory errors: the
Deese-Roediger-McDermott,
or DRM, paradigm (Deese 1959;
Roediger and McDermott 1995).
I am fascinated because these errors display a blend of success and failure (on
which I will elaborate on below). In the paper, I argue that they are best
viewed as a distinct type of error, misremembering.
I go on to argue that we lack a theory of memory that
can explain misremembering. I divide theories of memory into two broad groups:
traditional Archival accounts and
contemporary Constructive ones. Each
is insensitive to the explanatory demands of misremembering errors, but in a
distinct way. In short, Archival accounts do well at explaining memory’s
successes and Constructive accounts do well at explaining memory’s failures.
But since misremembering errors involve success and failure, they present a challenge to both.
To see the point, let us turn first to the
DRM. In this paradigm, participants are presented with a list of related items
to memorize and then are later quizzed about which items were on the list. Here’s
an example (you are welcome to try this out on a friend! The standard results
are fairly easy to obtain):
List:
RIPE
CITRUS
VEGETABLE
VEGETABLE
JUICE
COCKTAIL
BANANA
BANANA
BASKET
BOWL
BOWL
SALAD
BERRY
KIWI
APPLE
CHERRY
After a short break, participants are asked
three types of recognition questions:
- Was JUICE on the list?
- Was RADIO on the list?
- Was FRUIT on the list?
Most participants do well with questions
1 and 2; JUICE was clearly on the list and RADIO was clearly not. The
difficulty comes with question 3, about words that are related to those on the
list but were not actually included. Many participants claim to recognize FRUIT
as being on the list. They report recognizing it as often as words that were on
the list, like JUICE, and in some cases, will even provide details of what went
through their minds when they heard this word (which, of course, is a false
memory because the word was never presented). Results from the DRM are robust;
they are well replicated across changes in stimuli, retention interval, and
even warnings against making such errors. The DRM results are so
well-established, in fact, that this paradigm is often used as a baseline
against which to measure the efficacy of other experimental manipulations.
Hopefully it is now clear why I
characterize these errors as a blend of success and failure. Participants in
the DRM appear to both forget and remember what was on the list. When a
participant claims to recognize FRUIT, she errs. But to claim that FRUIT and JUICE
were on the list, while RADIO was not, relies on successful retention of the
list-learning event.
I
argue that DRM errors are instances of misremembering, which I define as
follows:
Misremembering is a memory error that relies on
successful retention of the targeted event. When a person misremembers, her
report is inaccurate and yet the error is explicable only on the assumption
that she has retained information from the event that her representation
mischaracterizes.
Misremembering errors do not
require a laboratory. They are familiar from everyday experience. When
reflecting on a past party, you might recall that your aunt arrived late when
it was actually your cousin, or that this was the occasion when your aunt told
a particularly funny story, when this actually occurred at a different
gathering.
With a clear understanding of
these errors to hand, my next task in the paper is to see whether either of the
two standard approaches to memory—the Archival View and the
Constructive View—can explain these errors.
The
Archival View is the traditional, default view of memory, according to which
memory is a preservative capacity directed at the past. The view is shaped
around the assumption that—at least some of the time—we form and retain
discrete representations of our past experiences. This account does well at
capturing what happens in cases of remembering, but Archivalists struggle to accommodate
DRM errors because they are at a loss to explain how one could retain
information from a past event and yet fail to produce an accurate
representation of that event when remembering. If I have stored the list of
words, so I can recognize JUICE and reject RADIO, then why would I also then
err and “recognize” FRUIT?
Proponents
of the Constructive View argue that memory is a capacity for building (i.e.,
constructing) representations of past events. Memory still preserves information
from the past, but this information is retained in a generalized way; there is
no retention of information from particular past events. This enables the
Constructivist to explain why memory errors so often involve errors and
distortions. But appeal to the various influences on retrieval can only explain
so much. The Constructive approach leaves out a key influence on misremembering
errors like those of the DRM: information retained from the particular past
event. The relationship between FRUIT and JUICE influences participant errors
on the task, but so does the particular past event of learning the list.
In the
paper, I provide more detail about versions of Constructivism and explore many
alternative ways that proponents of each view could explain the DRM effect in
particular and misremembering in general. I conclude that neither the Archival
or Constructive account can provide a plausible account of these errors.
Fortunately,
the explanatory limitations of the Archival and Constructive Views are
complementary, which suggests a way forward. I think that explaining
misremembering will require a hybrid theory of memory, combining the Archival
View’s commitment to retention of discrete memory traces with the Constructive
View’s approach to retrieval. In the paper, I only sketch the beginnings of
what such an account might look like. Providing a detailed account of this
hybrid view is the task of my current and future work.