Skip to main content

Eighth Meeting of SEFA



The eighth meeting of the Spanish Society for Analytic Philosophy (SEFA) took place in Oviedo, Spain, from 10th–12th November, 2016. Over 70 speakers presented their research during the three-day conference, and here I summarise just some of the papers given on topics in the philosophy of mind and epistemology.

Juan Comesaña, of the University of Arizona, gave the first keynote talk, on rationality and falsity in belief and action. He proposed that some false beliefs can be rational. Consider, for instance, the pre-Einsteinian belief in the additivity of speed. There is a persuasive sense in which this belief was once rational, even though strictly speaking it is false. In defence of the notion that falsehoods can sometimes be rationally believed, Comesaña argued that rational action requires rational belief, and that we can sometimes act rationally on the basis of false beliefs. He demonstrated that this view survives translation into a traditional decision theoretic framework of credence ascription, and that when we update credences based on false propositions, we can be considered to be doing so rationally.


Matilde Aliffi, of the University of Birmingham, presented her research on the relation between the content of emotions and the content of appraisals. She argued that (i) the content of the emotion is not identical to the content of the appraisal which activated it, and (ii) the content of the emotion supervenes on the value presented in the appraisal. In defence of (i), Aliffi presented a range of situations in which the content of the emotion and the content of the appraisal appear to come apart. In defence of (ii), she demonstrated that which emotion is activated depends on the kind of appraisal that takes place.

Josefa Toribio, of the Catalan Institution for Research and Advanced Studies, argued against the recent turn in the implicit cognition literature which models implicit attitudes as propositionally structured states. This view hinges on studies which purport to show that implicit attitudes can be updated in light of evidential considerations. Toribio argued that these studies may only show that the behaviours driven by implicit attitudes are modulated, rather than there being a change in the attitudes themselves. She further argued that considerations which emphasise the challenges posed by structural social injustice offer better support for answering the structural question in favour of an associationist view.


I presented a paper on implicit bias, awareness and moral responsibility. Recent work in this area (e.g. Holroyd, 2015), shows that we do not necessarily fail to meet the epistemic criteria for moral responsibility for implicitly biased action. I raised some problems for translating the conclusions of this work (which relies on laboratory-based studies) to the world beyond the lab, including the puzzle of how to recognise bias amongst confounding variables in real-world scenarios. I then offered some reasons for thinking the conclusions of this work still stands, albeit with some restrictions. Firstly, patterns of bias in our behaviour become easier to spot over time. Secondly, the ability of subjects of bias to correctly identify bias in others’ behaviour raises our expectations on biased actors to recognise their own biases. 

Raamy Majeed, of the University of Cambridge, presented his research on recalcitrant emotions. (Raamy discusses his work in more detail on our blog here.) Recalcitrant emotions are those which conflict with an individual’s judgements, such as fear of flying, whilst judging flying to be safe. Majeed pointed out a gap in the literature in determining the precise nature of the recalcitrance in question. He argued that the best way to account for the recalcitrant nature of these emotions is to consider them as cognitively impenetrable. He presented some empirical evidence to support this conclusion, including research that shows that the neural processes governing particular emotional responses are not amenable to cognitive control, and the finding that we are better at regulating emotions generated by top-down rather than bottom-up processes.


A further keynote was given by Lucy O’Brien, of University College London, who presented a theory of shame. She first demonstrated the shortcomings of existing models. One on model, shame is failing to meet the demands of one’s own personal ethics. O’Brien pointed out cases in which one feels shame without violating one’s own ethics, which cannot be accounted for by this first model. On another model, shame is merely exposing oneself to another. O’Brien demonstrated the logical consequences of this view as somewhat absurd: we lack control over a number of features that we expose to others, and yet this does not immediately cause shame. O’Brien presented an alternative view on which shame is a form of interpersonal self-consciousness, involving the likelihood of degradation or expulsion from the social group of which one is a part.

Casey Doyle, from St. Hilda’s College of the University of Cambridge, gave a paper on self-deception and reason-giving. Doyle argued that there are cases of being self-deceived about ones reasons for action and belief that manifest a distinctly non-epistemic failure. He distinguished reason-giving from an agential perspective in which stating that one believes p because q is constitutive of believing p for that reason, from reason-giving from a ‘spectatorial’ perspective in which one is simply trying to accurately represent a feature of the world. He then argued that, in a particular class of cases, self-deception about reasons involves a confusion of these two perspectives. A subject who is self-deceived about their reasons or motives presents themselves as speaking from the agential perspective. However, they are in fact speaking from the spectatorial perspective, forming a belief about their reasons caused by their desires. For Doyle, these subjects violate a constitutive norm of the practice of reason-giving.
  

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...