Skip to main content

Responding to Stereotyping


In this post Kathy Puddifoot (pictured above), Research Fellow at the University of Birmingham, summarises her paper on "Responding to Stereotyping", which is forthcoming in a special issue of Philosophical Explorations on false but useful beliefs. The special issue is guest edited by Lisa Bortolotti and Ema Sullivan-Bissett and is inspired by project PERFECT's interests in belief.

Women occupy only thirteen percent of jobs in scientific fields in the United Kingdom. Suppose that as a result of being exposed to accurate depictions of this situation, say, in the news media, you form a stereotype associating science with men. This association influences your automatic responses to individuals. For example, if you hear about a great feat of engineering you automatically assume that the person who achieved it is a man. Is it a good thing that your judgements are automatically influenced by this scientist stereotype?

A natural thought is that if you want to be egalitarian, doing the ethical thing, then you should not engage in stereotyping. You should assume, for example, that any achievement in engineering is equally likely to be achieved by a man or a woman. In contrast, if your aim is to make correct judgements, it is not a bad thing to be influenced by the stereotype because it reflects reality. My paper challenges this thought.

I show that stereotyping leads to errors in judgement regardless of whether the stereotype that is applied reflects reality because the application of the stereotype can lead to the distorted perception of an individual. For instance, the abovementioned scientist stereotype can lead ambiguous behaviours displayed by female scientists, such as errors in speech made when explaining complex scientific ideas, to be viewed as evidence of lack scientific expertise.

I show that one can be more likely to achieve one’s epistemic goals, making correct judgements about individuals, as well as being egalitarian, if one responds in ways that fail to reflect certain social realities, thereby avoiding errors associated with stereotyping. This means that the best thing to do in order to make a correct judgement is more often than might be expected the egalitarian thing: avoiding stereotyping.

I argue that cognitions that fail to reflect social realities, such as the underrepresentation of women in the sciences, can be epistemically innocent. Although they bring epistemic costs, increasing the chance of errors in judgement in some specific circumstances, they also bring significant epistemic benefits, reducing the chance of errors in judgement in many responses to individuals.



My argument provides a response to a defence of stereotyping. A person might defend an act of stereotyping on the basis that by stereotyping they are merely tracking the truth (e.g. “Well more scientists are men, so my judgements are most likely to track reality if I associate science with men”). Sometimes it will be possible to respond by showing that the stereotype does not reflect reality (e.g. “Actually, scientists are just as likely to be women as men nowadays”), but where a response like this is not available my argument supplies an alternative response: i.e. even if the stereotype reflects reality it does not follow that judgements formed as a result of applying the stereotype will reflect reality. On the contrary, people are often more likely to make accurate judgements if they avoid stereotyping even where the stereotype reflects an aspect of social reality.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph